Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Explicit Cost-Effectiveness Thresholds in Health Care: A Kaleidoscope

  • Published:
Social Justice Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although the principles of cost-effectiveness analysis have been adopted by health systems worldwide, a large majority of countries remain reluctant to specify explicit threshold values for cost-effectiveness. Nonetheless, by aiming to benchmark what counts as a reasonable ‘price’ for health gains, the threshold value is a linchpin in the framework of health technology assessment, albeit also a controversial one. The desirability of thresholds depends largely on three claims: their intention to make resource allocation more efficient, their aspiration to make decision-making more transparent and their objective to make healthcare systems more sustainable. In this paper, we draw from various disciplines such as health economics but also psychology, anthropology, sociology, political sciences and ethics to discuss the many facets of these three values, related to the threshold debate. We discuss issues of allocative efficiency, fair decision-making, realpolitik, taboos, institutional justice and the rule of rescue. Based upon these considerations, which together substantiate the precautionary principle, we conclude that the case against thresholds is stronger than the case in favor and that most countries are right to be reluctant to use explicit threshold values.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. With the latter, we mean official, publicly available thresholds of what constitutes a cost-effective healthcare program (e.g., £30,000/QALY).

  2. The first is that of communal sharing, which divides social life into two groups (members and non-members) that both have different rights and obligations (a binary dichotomy). A typical example is the distinction between family members and non-family members, friends and non-friends, between citizens and non-citizens. Membership means an equal right to the benefits of the group, non-membership leads to no entitlements. The second sphere is that of authority ranking, based on one’s status and location in a social hierarchy (a lexical ordinal ranking of people). A typical example is the superior status of a person like the president or the king, having more authority than others because of their higher place in the hierarchy. The third sphere is that of equality matching where we settle scores between equal partners (allowing to measure). This is the sphere of equals, colleagues or friends inviting one another over for dinner, for example. Within this sphere, a ‘tit-for-tat’ reciprocity between equals dominates (e.g., after a certain amount of time, we’re expected to return a dinner invitation). The fourth sphere is that of market pricing, where a single metric (like money, for instance) makes valuation and comparison of a large number of entities possible (allowing ratios and all kinds of calculations and weighing of costs and benefits) (Fiske & Tetlock, 1997).

  3. An interesting illustration can be found in the ‘Danner Commission’ experiment (Shoemaker & Tetlock, 2012), in which participants were informed about a fictionalized public health program and its recommended reforms in the light of efficient use of public resources. If the reforms were followed, the program could save 200 lives, at a cost of $100 million. If the program continued at the previous year’s budget of $200 million, 400 lives could be saved. In the experiment, the Commission recommended not to continue and instead, to redirect the saving of $100 million to other important public uses. This is a clear example of a policy choice that requires explicit valuation of human life. The researchers investigated people’s response to different explanation strategies. For two groups, the Commission offered a smokescreen strategy that took either a utilitarian form (‘After weighing relevant costs and benefits, the Commission concludes that this is the right thing to do’) or moralistic form (‘Based on its analysis, the Commission concludes that morally this is the right thing to do’). For a third group, the decision grounds were presented transparently (‘The cost of saving the additional 200 lives (at $500,000 per life) is too high given other important priorities’). In the first two groups (where the trade-offs remained implicit), around 72% supported the recommendation. In the third group (with the explicit trade-off), approval went down to 35%.

References

  • Afzali, H. H. A., Karnon, J., & Sculpher, M. (2016). Should the lambda (λ) remain silent? PharmacoEconomics, 34, 323–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertram, M. Y., Lauer, J. A., De Joncheere, K., Edejer, T., Hutubessy, R., Kieny, M. P., et al. (2016). Cost-effectiveness thresholds: Pros and cons. Bulletin of the World Health Organization, 94(12), 925–930.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Birch, S., & Gafni, A. (2006). Information created to evade reality (ICER): Things we should not look to for answers. Pharmacoeconomics, 11, 1121–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birch, S., & Gafni, A. (2015). On the margins of health economics: A response to ‘resolving NICE’s nasty dilemma. Health Economics, Policy & Law, 10, 183–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., Brock, D., Daniels, N., & Wikler, D. (2000). From chance to choice: Genetics and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Burggraeve, R. (1995). The ethical meaning of money in the thought of Emmanuel Levinas. Ethical Perspectives, 2(2), 85–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burggraeve, R. (2015). Ethics as crisis: Levinas’ contribution to a humane society. In R. Serpytyte (Ed.), Emmanuel Levinas: A radical thinker in the time of crisis (pp. 9–26). Vilnius: Vilnius University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callahan, D. (1991a). Ethics and priority setting in oregon. Health Affairs, 10(2), 78–87.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Callahan, D. (1991b). The oregon initiative: Ethics and priority setting. Health Matrix, 1(2), 157–170.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Claxton, K., Martin, S., Soares, M., Rice, N., Spackman, E., Hinde, S., et al. (2015). Methods for the estimation of the National Institute for Health and Care Excellence cost-effectiveness threshold. Health Technol Assess, 19(14), 1–503. v–vi.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Clement, F. M., Harris, A., Li, J. J., Yong, K., Lee, K. M., & Manns, B. J. (2009). Using effectiveness and cost-effectiveness to make drug coverage decisions: A comparison of Britain, Australia, and Canada. JAMA, 302(13), 1437–1443.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, I. G., Daniels, N., & Eyal, N. (2015). Identified versus statistical lives. An interdisciplinary perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cookson, R., McDaid, D., & Maynard, A. (2001). Wrong SIGN, NICE mess: Is national guidance distorting allocation of resources? BMJ, 323, 5–743.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Creadon, M. (1997). The ocean denied. Time, 149, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (1996). Justice and justification. Reflective equilibrium in theory and practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (1999). Enabling democratic deliberation: How managed care organisations ought to make decisions about coverage for new technologies. In S. Macedo (Ed.), Deliberative politics: Essays on democracy and disagreement (pp. 198–210). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (2001). Justice, health, and healthcare. American Journal of Bioethics, 1(2), 2–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (2008). Just health: Meeting health needs fairly. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N., & Sabin, J. E. (1997). Limits to health care: Fair procedures, democratic deliberation, and the legitimacy problem for insurers. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 26, 303–350.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N., & Sabin, J. (1998). The ethics of accountability and the reform of managed care organisations. Health Affairs, 17(5), 50–69.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N., & Sabin, J. E. (2002). Setting limits fairly: Can we learn to share medical resources?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Danzon, P. M., et al. (2018). Objectives, budgets, thresholds, and opportunity costs-a health economics approach: An ISPOR special task force report [4]. Value Health, 21(2), 140–145.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes (1994) Oeuvres et Lettres, Paris: Gallimard. (Ed. and Trans. G. Heffernan). Discourse on the method, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Drummond, M., Sculpher, M. J., Torrance, G., O’Brien, G., & Stoddard, G. (2005). Methods for the economic evaluation of health care programmes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. (1925). Moral education. A study in the theory and application of the sociology of education (Ed. E.K. Wilson, E.K. Wilson & H. Schnurer, Transl.) (1973). New York: Free Press.

  • Dworkin, R. (1993). Justice in the distribution of health care, repr. In M. Clayton; A. Williams (eds.), The ideal of equality, 2002 (pp. 203–222). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Dworkin, R. (1994). Justice and the high cost of health, repr. in id., Sovereign Virtue. In The theory and practice of equality, 2000 (pp. 307–319). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Eichler, H. G., Kong, S. X., Gerth, W. C., Mavros, P., & Jonsson, B. (2004). Use of cost-effectiveness analysis in health-care resource allocation decision-making: How are cost-effectiveness thresholds expected to emerge? Value Health, 7(5), 518–528.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, A., & Tetlock, P. (1997). ‘Taboo trade-offs: Reactions to transactions that transgress the spheres of justice. Political Psychology, 18(2), 255–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey, M., & Schokkaert, E. (2012). Equity in health and health care. In M. V. Pauly, T. G. McGuire, & P. P. Barros (Eds.), Handbook of health economics (Vol. 2, pp. 1003–1092). New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gafni, A., & Birch, S. (2006). Incremental cost-effectiveness ratios (ICERs): The silence of the lambda. Social Science & Medicine, 62, 2091–2100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • George, B., Harris, A., & Mitchell, A. (2001). Cost-effectiveness analysis and the consistency of decision making: Evidence from pharmaceutical reimbursement in australia (1991 to 1996). Pharmacoeconomics, 19(11), 1103–1109.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Gold, M., Siegel, J., Russell, L., & Weinstein, M. C. (1994). Cost-effectiveness in health and medicine. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadorn, D. C. (1991). The oregon priority-setting exercise: Quality of life and public policy. Hastings Center Report, 21(3), 11–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ham, C. (1997). Priority setting in health care: Learning from international experience. Health Policy, 42(1), 49–66.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. M. (2006). Valuing health. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 34(3), 246–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. (2015). Valuing health. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jecker, N. S. (2013). Justice between age groups: An objection to the prudential lifespan approach. AJOB, 13(8), 3–15.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Jonsen, A. R. (1986). Bentham in a box: Technology assessment and health care allocation. Law, Medicine, and Health Care, 14, 172–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1969). Totality and infinity. An essay in exteriority. (A. Lingis, Transl.). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (1981). Otherwise than being and beyond essence. (A. Lingis, Transl.). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (1987). Time and the other. (R.A. Cohen, Transl.). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (1990). Nine talmudic readings (A. Aronowicz, Transl.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Levinas, E. (2006). Thinking-of-the-other. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marseille, E., Larson, B., Kazi, D. S., Kahn, J. G., & Rosen, S. (2015). Thresholds for the cost-effectiveness of interventions: Alternative approaches. Bull World Health Organ, 93(2), 118–124.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • McCabe, C., Claxton, K., & Culyer, A. J. (2008). The NICE cost-effectiveness threshold: What it is and what that means. Pharmacoeconomics, 26(9), 733–744.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • McGraw, P. A., Davis, D. F., Scott, S. E., & Tetlock, P. E. (2016). The price of not putting a price on love. Judgement and Decision Making, 11(1), 40–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGraw, P. A., & Tetlock, P. E. (2005). Taboo trade-offs, relational framing, and the acceptability of exchanges. Journal of Consumer Psychology, 15(1), 2–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mckie, J., & Richardson, J. (2003). The rule of rescue. Social Science & Medicine, 56, 2407–2419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2000). The costs of tragedy: Some moral limits of cost-benefit analysis. Journal of Legal Studies, 29, 1005–1036.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearson, S. D., & Rawlins, M. D. (2005). Quality, innovation, and value for money: NICE and the British National Health Service. JAMA, 294(20), 2618–2622.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sabik, L. M., & Lie, R. K. (2008). Priority setting in health care: Lessons from the experiences of eight countries. International Journal for Equity in Health, 7, 4.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Schildmann, J., & Vollmann, J. (2017). Personalized medicine: Conceptual, ethical and empirical challenges. In T. Schramme & S. Edwards (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of medicine. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoemaker, P. J. H., & Tetlock, P. E. (2012). Taboo scenarios: How to think about the unthinkable. California Management Review, 54(2), 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schokkaert, E. (2009). Willingness to pay and solidarity. In M. Wynants (Ed.), In sickness and in health. The future of medicine (pp. 99–111). Brussel: VUB Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schokkaert, E. (2011). Philosophers and taboo trade-offs in health care. In A. Gosseries & Y. Vanderborght (Eds.), Arguing about justice. Essays for Philippe Van Parijs (pp. 303–309). Louvain-la-Neuve: Presses universitaires de Louvain.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segall, S. (2009). Health, luck and justice. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sendi, P., Gafni, A., & Birch, S. (2002). Opportunity costs and uncertainty in the economic evaluation of healthcare interventions. Health Economics, 11, 23–31.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2014). Philosophy and the precautionary principle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock, P. (2003). Thinking the unthinkable: Sacred values and taboo cognitions. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(7), 320–324.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock, P. E., Peterson, R. S., & Lerner, J. S. (1996). Revising the value pluralism model: Incorporating social content and context postulates. In C. Seligman, J. Olson, & M. Zanna (Eds.), Values. Eight annual Ontario symposium on personality and social psychology (pp. 25–51). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock, P., et al. (2000). The psychology of the unthinkable: Taboo trade-offs, forbidden base rates and heretical counterfacts. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 78, 853–870.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Thokala, P., Ochalek, J., Leech, A. A., & Tong, T. (2018). Cost-effectiveness thresholds: The past, the present and the future. Pharmacoeconomics, 36(5), 509–522.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Vollmann, J., Sandow, V., Wäscher, S., & Schildman, J. (2015). The ethics of personalised medicine: Critical perspectives. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinstein, M., & Zeckhauser, R. (1973). Critical ratios and efficient allocation. Journal of Public Economics, 2(2), 147–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • WHO. (2014). Choosing interventions that are cost-effective. Available from: http://www.who.int/choice/en.

  • Williams, A. H., & Cookson, R. A. (2006). Equity-efficiency trade-offs in health technology assessment. International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care, 22(1), 1–9.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Woods, B., et al. (2016). Country-level cost-effectiveness thresholds: Initial estimates and the need for further research. Value Health, 19(8), 929–935.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Previous versions of this paper were presented at the Annual Conference of the European Association of Centers for Medical Ethics (EACME) in Leuven, September 2016, at the international symposium on ‘Violence of Money’ organized by the Institute of Philosophy (University of Leuven) in January 2018, at the international workshop on ‘Ethics and Economics of Health Care’ organized by Tilburg University in March 2018 and at the international Intensive Course on ‘Justice and Priority Setting in Health Care’ in March 2018. We are grateful to all the participants of these meeting, for their inspiring comments on earlier thoughts. Special thanks goes to: Arnold Burms, Roger Burggraeve, Herman De Dijn, Bart Engelen, Dan Hausman, Erik Schokkaert, Paul Schotsmans, Ruud Termeulen, Antoon Vandevelde and Marcel Verweij. Each of them have, in own and various ways, inspired us to tackle this issue from a multidimensional kaleidoscope perspective and convinced us of the significance of doing it this way.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jeroen Luyten.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Luyten, J., Denier, Y. Explicit Cost-Effectiveness Thresholds in Health Care: A Kaleidoscope. Soc Just Res 32, 155–171 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11211-018-0322-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11211-018-0322-9

Keywords

Navigation