Skip to main content
Log in

Belief-consistent Pareto dominance

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Bulletin Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The classic Pareto criterion claims that all voluntary trades, even on the grounds of heterogeneous beliefs, should be encouraged. I argue that a trade without hope for Pareto improvement remains controversial. I introduce and characterize a notion of belief-consistent Pareto dominance to formalize this argument, which, in addition to unanimity of preferences, requires all rankings in a trade to be supported by some common beliefs that must coincide with the agents’ beliefs about the events on which all agents agree.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In advance, preference aggregation with heterogeneous beliefs has a similar flavor. Gilboa et al. (2004) offered an example in which two parties do not receive mutual gains from a duel, but each party is expecting to benefit at the expense of the other party. Because both parties cannot be correct, Mongin (1997) argued that such unanimity is spurious.

  2. See page 193 of Kreps (2012) for the details of the story.

  3. Savage (1972) identified the following three views of probability: objective, subjective and necessary. Because how to estimate the necessary probability is unclear, its application in economics is very limited. I will not discuss this issue here as it is not relevant to the discussion, and more detail is provided in Savage (1972)

  4. An objection to such a view is presented in Morris (1995).

  5. See Aumann (1987) for further discussion regarding this argument. An objection to such a view in the preference aggregation setting is provided in Mongin and Pivato (2016).

  6. Following directly from GSS, our notion of Pareto dominance is more restrictive than standard Pareto dominance, which states that allocation f Pareto dominates g if \(f\succsim _i g\) for all i and \(f\succ _j g\) for some j. In contrast, our notion requires all traders strictly prefer f, ruling out the possibility of indifference among traders. We refer to p1416 of GSS for further elaboration.

  7. It is actually a \(\lambda \)-system. Recall that a collection of events is a \(\lambda \)-system if it includes a universal set and is closed under complement and disjoint union.

  8. Although the collection of such unanimous events is, generally a \(\lambda \)-system, our simplification is without loss of generality. One can assume a general \(\lambda \)-system. Then, the condition (ii) of Theorem 1 should hold for each possible partition generated by this \(\lambda \)-system.

References

  • Allais, M.: Le Comportement de l’Homme Rationnel devant le Risque: Critique des Postulats et Axiomes de l’Ecole Americaine. Econometrica 21(4), 503–546 (1953)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aumann, R.: Correlated equilibrium as an expression of Bayesian rationality. Econometrica 55(1), 1–18 (1987)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blume, L., Cogley, T., Easley, D., Sargent, T., Tsyrennikov, V.: Welfare, Paternalism and Market Incompleteness. Working Paper (2014)

  • Brunnermeier, M., Simsek, A., Xiong, W.: A welfare criterion for models with distorted beliefs. Q. J. Econ. 129(4), 1753–1797 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gayer, G., Gilboa, I., Samuelson, L., Schmeidler, D.: Pareto efficiency with different beliefs. J. Legal Stud. 43(S2), S151–S171 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., Samet, D., Schmeidler, D.: Utilitarian aggregation of beliefs and tastes. J. Polit. Econ. 112(4), 932–938 (2004)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., Samuelson, L., Schmeidler, D.: No-Betting-Pareto dominance. Econometrica 82(4), 1405–1442 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D.: Microeconomic Foundations I: Choice and Competitive Markets. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mongin, P.: Spurious unanimity and the Pareto principle. Econ. Philos. 1, 1–22, 11 (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mongin, P., Pivato, M.: Social Preference Under Twofold Uncertainty. Working Paper (2016)

  • Morris, S.: The common prior assumption in economic theory. Econ. Philos. 11(2), 227–253 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, E., Weyl, G.: An FDA for financial innovation: applying the insurable interest doctrine to twenty-first-century financial markets. Northwest. Univ. Law Rev. 107, 1307 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L.: The Foundations of Statistics. Dover, New York (1972)

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, G.: Is Arbitrage Socially Beneficial? Working Paper (2007)

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Xiangyu Qu.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

I thank Anotine Billot, Itzhak Gilboa, Marcus Pivato, and David Schmeidler for discussions. I especially appreciate helpful comments from a referee.

Appendix: Proofs

Appendix: Proofs

Proof of Theorem

We know that a finite partition \(\{E_1,\ldots ,E_N\}\) generates the set of unanimous events \(\Lambda \). We also know that probability p on \(\Lambda \) satisfies that \(p(E)=p_i(E)\) for \(i\in \mathcal {I}\) and \(E\in \Lambda \).

Pick a pair of allocations f and g. Since both allocations are simple and measurable, there is also a finite partition of S, \((A_j)_{j\le J}\), such that both f and g are constant over each \(A_j\). For each \(n\le N\) and \(j\le J\), we define

$$\begin{aligned} B_{nj}=E_n\cup A_j. \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, \((B_{nj})_{n\le N; j\le J}\) consists a coarser finite partition of S. Thus, we use \(f(B_{nj})\) and \(g(B_{nj})\) to denote the outcomes in X that f and g, respectively, assume over event \(B_{nj}\) for each \(n\le N\) and \(j\le J\). The theorem characterizes the definition of Belief-consistent Pareto dominance, namely, there exists a probability measure \(p^*\in \Delta (\Lambda )\) such that for each \(i\in \mathcal {I}(f,g)\),

$$\begin{aligned} \int _S u_i(f)\mathrm {d}p^*>\int _S g_i(f)\mathrm {d}p^* \end{aligned}$$
(1)

It is equivalent to the existence of a probability vector \((p^*(n,j))_{n\le N; j\le J}\in \Delta (N\times J)\) such that

$$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{\begin{array}{c} n\le N \\ j\le J \end{array}}p^*(n,j)u_i(f(B_{nj}))>\sum _{\begin{array}{c} n\le N\\ j\le J \end{array}}p^*(n,j)u_i(g(B_{nj}))\quad \text {and }\nonumber \\&\quad \sum _{j\le J}p^*(n,j)=p(E_n),\quad \text {for all }n\le N. \end{aligned}$$
(2)

Notice that if a probability measure \(p^*\in \Delta (\Lambda )\) exists, it can reduce to a probability vector \(p^*(n,j)\) satisfying Eq. (2). Conversely, if a probability vector \(p^*(n,j)\) exists, we can extend it to a unanimous probability measure on \((S,\Sigma )\), which satisfies Eq. (1).

Condition (i) in Theorem 1 is equivalent to the existence of \(p^*(n,j)\) satisfying Eq. (2). To our end, we will show that the existence of \(p^*(n,j)\) is equivalent to Condition (ii) in Theorem 1. To see such equivalence, we construct a two-person zero-sum game. In such constructed game, we will show that \(p^*(n,j)\) satisfying Eq. (2) is equivalent to Condition (ii) according to minmax theorem for two-person zero-sum games.

For each \(n\le N\), let \(B^n=\{B_{n1},\ldots ,B_{nJ}\}\). The strategy for player I is

$$\begin{aligned} (b^1,\ldots ,b^N)\in B=B^1\times \cdots \times B^N. \end{aligned}$$

The strategy for player II is \(i\in \mathcal {I}(f,g)\). Given a strategy profile (bi), the payoff for player I is defined as

$$\begin{aligned} U(b,i)=\displaystyle \sum ^N_{n=1}p(E_n)[u_i(f(b^n))-u_i(g(b^n))]. \end{aligned}$$

Player I may use mixed strategy and a simplex \(\Delta (B)\) represents the set of mixed strategy for player I. Therefore, should player I chooses mixed strategy \(\sigma \) and player II chooses i, the payoff for player I is

$$\begin{aligned} U(\sigma ,i)=\displaystyle \sum _{(b^1,\ldots ,b^N)\in B}\sigma (b^1,\ldots ,b^N)\left[ \displaystyle \sum ^N_{n=1}p(E_n)(u_i(f(b^n))-u_i(g(b^n)))\right] . \end{aligned}$$

For any event \(B_{nj}\), we denote

$$\begin{aligned} \sigma (B_{nj})=\sum _{\begin{array}{c} b^n\ne B_{nj}\\ (b^1,\ldots ,b^N)\in B \end{array}}\sigma (b^1,\ldots ,b^N). \end{aligned}$$

Notice that \(\sum _{j\le J}\sigma (B_{nj})=1\). Therefore, the payoff for player I given strategy profile \((\sigma ,i)\) can be written as

$$\begin{aligned} U(\sigma ,i)=\displaystyle \sum _{n\le N}p(E_n)\sum _{j\le J}\sigma (B_{nj})[u_i(f(B_{nj})-u_i(g(B_{nj})] \end{aligned}$$

If there exists \(\sigma \in \Delta (B)\) such that, for every pure strategy of player II, \(i\in \mathcal {I}(f,g)\),

$$\begin{aligned} U(\sigma ,i)>0, \end{aligned}$$

then we can claim that there exists \(p^*(n,j)\) satisfying Eq. (2). (To see this, simply define \(p^*(n,j)=p(E_n)\cdot \sigma (B_{nj})\). Then, \(\sum _{j\le J}p^*(n,j)=p(E_n)\cdot \sum _{j\le J}\sigma (B_{nj})=p(E_n)\).)

Therefore, existence of \(p^*(n,j)\) satisfying Eq. (2) is equivalent to the existence of \(\sigma \in \Delta (B)\) such that, for every mixed strategy of play II, \(\lambda \in \Delta (\mathcal {I}(f,g))\),

$$\begin{aligned} \displaystyle \sum _{i\in \mathcal {I}(f,g)}\lambda (i)\cdot U(\sigma , i)>0. \end{aligned}$$

In other words

$$\begin{aligned} \displaystyle \max _{\sigma \in \Delta (B)}\min _{\lambda \in \Delta (\mathcal {I}(f,g))}\sum _i\lambda (i)\cdot U(\sigma ,i)>0. \end{aligned}$$

According to the minmax theorem for two-person zero-sum games, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \displaystyle \min _{\lambda \in \Delta (\mathcal {I}(f,g))}\max _{\sigma \in \Delta (B)}\sum _i\lambda (i)\cdot U(\sigma ,i)>0. \end{aligned}$$

That is to say, there exists \(p^*(n,j)\) satisfying Eq. (2) if and only if for any \(\lambda \), there exists \(\sigma \in \Delta (B)\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} \displaystyle \sum _{i\in \mathcal {I}(f,g)}\lambda (i)\displaystyle \sum _{(b^1,\ldots ,b^N)\in B}\sigma (b^1,\ldots ,b^N)\left[ \displaystyle \sum ^N_{n=1}p(E_n)(u_i(f(b^n))-u_i(g(b^n)))\right] >0. \end{aligned}$$

Notice that for each \(\lambda \), such a \(\sigma \in \Delta (B)\) exists if and only if there exists a unit vector, namely, there exists \((b^1,\ldots ,b^N)\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} \displaystyle \sum _{i\in \mathcal {I}(f,g)}\lambda (i) \displaystyle \sum ^N_{n=1}p(E_n)(u_i(f(b^n))-u_i(g(b^n)))>0. \end{aligned}$$

This is the same case that there exists \(s_n\in E_n\) for each \(n\le N\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} \displaystyle \sum _{i\in \mathcal {I}(f,g)}\lambda (i) \displaystyle \sum ^N_{n=1}p(E_n)(u_i(f(s_n))-u_i(g(s_n)))>0. \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Qu, X. Belief-consistent Pareto dominance. Econ Theory Bull 8, 219–229 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-019-00178-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-019-00178-0

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation