Skip to main content
Log in

On the consumer problem under an informational externality

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Bulletin Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We use the Hendricks and Kovenock (RAND J Econ 20(2):164–182, 1989) framework to study the consumer problem under an informational externality. The informational externality arises when each consumer of a social network is endowed with private information regarding the quality of a good. In such situations, the past purchasing decisions of the consumers are informative and, thus, are used as partially revealing signals of private information. Asymmetric information and the observability of actions render the consumer problem dynamic and strategic because the purchasing decision of a consumer affects the other consumers’ future payoffs through the learning process. We show that there exists a unique symmetric Bayesian–Nash equilibrium. The informational externality increases the likelihood for a consumer to refrain from purchasing the good immediately to make a more informed decision in the future.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Observational learning refers to situations in which agents learn from observing each other’s decisions. Observational learning is different from social learning. Social learning refers to situations in which agents learn from communicating with each other.

  2. Private information arises from the heterogeneous processing of, and exposure to public information, such as advertising and reviews.

  3. The flow of information is endogenous when neither agent undertakes the action, but it is assumed to be revealed once either agent undertakes the action.

  4. Here, the action of the other agent forms an informational externality.

  5. Another related literature considers how agents learn from communicating information to each other. For instance, Ellison and Fudenberg (1993, 1995) examine word-of-mouth communication under exogenously specified rules for behavior and social learning, while Vettas (1997) study how agents communicate information about product quality.

  6. While Gale and Kariv (2003) substitute sequential for simultaneous moves, the consumer problem remains static.

  7. The net utility is gross utility minus price where price is fixed and exogenous.

  8. Random variables are upper case and realizations are lower case with a circumflex accent.

  9. For \(Z \subset {\mathbb {R}}\), consumer i’s probability that \({\hat{\mu }} \in Z\) is \(\int _{\mu \in Z} \xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{i}) \text {d} \mu \) in period 1.

  10. If a consumer purchases the good in period 1, then he automatically exercises the outside option in period 2.

  11. In a full-information environment, consumer i is static and nonstrategic, i.e., he purchases the good if and only if \({\hat{\mu }} > 0\).

  12. Formally, for \(s > s^{\prime }\),

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{\xi (x^{\prime } \vert s^{\prime })}{\xi (x^{\prime } \vert s)} > \frac{\xi (x \vert s^{\prime })}{\xi (x \vert s)}. \end{aligned}$$
    (10)

    if and only if \(x > x^{\prime }\).

  13. By Jensen’s inequality,

    $$\begin{aligned} \int _{s_{B}\in {\mathbb {R}}}V_{A}^{**}({\hat{s}}_{A},s_{B})\phi (s_{B}|\mu )\text {d}s_{B} =&\int _{s_{B}\in {\mathbb {R}}}\max \{v\left( {\hat{s}}_{A},s_{B}\right) ,0\}\phi (s_{B}|\mu )\text {d}s_{B}, \end{aligned}$$
    (20)
    $$\begin{aligned} >&\max \left\{ \int _{s_{B}\in {\mathbb {R}}} v\left( {\hat{s}}_{A},s_{B}\right) \phi (s_{B}|\mu )\text {d}s_{B},0\right\} \end{aligned}$$
    (21)
    $$\begin{aligned} =&\max \{v_{1}({\hat{s}}_{A}),0\} \end{aligned}$$
    (22)

    as well as

    $$\begin{aligned} V_{A}({\hat{s}}_{A}) =&\max \left\{ v_{1}({\hat{s}}_{A}),\beta W({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B})\right\} , \end{aligned}$$
    (23)
    $$\begin{aligned} <&\max \left\{ v_{1}({\hat{s}}_{A}),\beta \max \left\{ 0,v_{1}({\hat{s}}_{A})\right\} \right\} , \end{aligned}$$
    (24)
    $$\begin{aligned} =&\max \{v_{1}({\hat{s}}_{A}),0\} \end{aligned}$$
    (25)

    since

    $$\begin{aligned}&\Pr [S_{B}\in {\mathcal {X}}_{B}|{\hat{s}}_{A}]\max \left\{ 0,v_{2}({\hat{s}}_{A},S_{B} \in {\mathcal {X}}_{B})\right\} \nonumber \\&\qquad + \beta \Pr [S_{B}\notin {\mathcal {X}}_{B}|{\hat{s}}_{A}] \max \left\{ 0,v_{2}({\hat{s}}_{A},S_{B}\notin {\mathcal {X}}_{B})\right\} <\max \left\{ 0,v_{1}({\hat{s}}_{A})\right\} . \end{aligned}$$
    (26)

    Combining (22) and (25) yields (27).

  14. Note that there is no incentive to manipulate the information since the externality is solely informational. If the good was short in supply, then sharing information might have an effect of a consumer’s probability to acquire the good. This would provide a reason for the consumers not to share information. For issues related to information sharing, see Hausch (1986) and Engelbrecht-Wiggans and Weber (1983) in the context of multi-unit auctions. In these papers, buyers have private information about the identical assets’ quality for sale which remains unknown, they want more than one of these assets (which are of unknown quality), they observe the submitted bids (in sequential auctions) and the asset’s quality is not revealed after the first stage. In such circumstances, there may be an incentive for a well-informed bidder to not reveal his signals in the first stage to deceive his opponent into believing that he has a bad signal and make a positive profit in the second stage.

References

  • Alexander-Cook, K., Bernhardt, D., Roberts, J.: Riding free on the signals of others. J. Public Econ. 67(1), 25–43 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banerjee, A.: A simple model of herd behavior. Q. J. Econ. 107(3), 797–817 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bikhchandani, S., Hirshleifer, D., Welch, I.: A theory of fads, fashion, custom, and cultural change as informational cascades. J. Political Econ. 100(5), 992–1026 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caplin, A., Leahy, J.: Business as usual, market crashes, and wisdom after the fact. Am. Econ. Rev. 89(3), 548–566 (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Caplin, A., Leahy, J.: Miracle on sixth avenue: information externalities and search. Econ. J. 108(446), 60–74 (1998)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caplin, A., Leahy, J.: Mass layoffs and unemployment. J. Monet. Econ. 46(1), 121–142 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chamley, C., Gale, D.: Information revelation and strategic delay in a model of investment. Econometrica 62(5), 1065–1085 (1994)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellison, G., Fudenberg, D.: Rules of thumb for social learning. J. Political Econ. 101(4), 612–643 (1993)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellison, G., Fudenberg, D.: Word-of-mouth communication and social learning. Q. J. Econ. 110(1), 93–125 (1995)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engelbrecht-Wiggans, R., Weber, R.J.: A sequential auction involving asymmetrically-informed bidders. Int. J. Game Theory 12(2), 123–127 (1983)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gale, D., Kariv, S.: Bayesian learning in social networks. Games Econ. Behav. 45(2), 329–346 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausch, D.B.: Multi-object auctions: sequential vs simultaneous sales. Manag. Sci. 32(12), 1599–1610 (1986)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendricks, K., Kovenock, D.: Asymmetric information, information externalities, and efficiency: the case of oil exploration. RAND J. Econ. 20(2), 164–182 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McFadden, D.L., Train, K.E.: Consumers’ evaluation of new products: learning from self and others. J. Political Econ. 104(4), 683–703 (1996)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, L., Sorensen, P.: Pathological outcomes of observational learning. Econometrica 68(2), 371–398 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vettas, N.: On the informational role of quantities: durable goods and consumers’ word-of-mouth communication. Int. Econ. Rev. 38(4), 915–944 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, J.: Strategic delay and the onset of investment cascades. RAND J. Econ. 28(1), 188–205 (1997)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marc Santugini.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Proofs

Proofs

The proofs are in the spirit of Hendricks and Kovenock (1989).

Proof of Proposition 3.4

From (7),

$$\begin{aligned}&\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) = v_{1}({\hat{s}}_{A}) - \beta W({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}), \end{aligned}$$
(28)
$$\begin{aligned}&\quad = \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} \mu \xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A}) \text {d} \mu - \beta \max \left\{ 0,\int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} \mu \Phi (S_{B} \in {\mathcal {X}}_{B} \vert \mu ) \xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A}) \text {d} \mu \right\} \nonumber \\&\qquad - \beta \max \left\{ 0,\int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} \mu \Phi (S_{B} \notin {\mathcal {X}}_{B} \vert \mu ) \xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A}) \text {d} \mu \right\} , \end{aligned}$$
(29)
$$\begin{aligned}&\quad = \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} \mu \left[ 1 - 1_{[{\hat{s}}_{A} \ge t_{1}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} \in {\mathcal {X}}_{B} \vert \mu ) - 1_{[ {\hat{s}}_{A} \ge t_{2} ]} \beta \Phi ( S_{B} \notin {\mathcal {X}}_{B} \vert \mu ) \right] \xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A}) \text {d} \mu , \end{aligned}$$
(30)
$$\begin{aligned}&\quad = \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} \mu \left[ 1 - 1_{[{\hat{s}}_{A}> t_{1}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} \in {\mathcal {X}}_{B} \vert \mu ) - 1_{[ {\hat{s}}_{A} > t_{2} ]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} \notin {\mathcal {X}}_{B} \vert \mu ) \right] \xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A}) \text {d} \mu \end{aligned}$$
(31)

be the difference between the value of purchasing the good in period 1, and the value of exercising the outside option in period 1. Note that \(\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) < 0\) for \({\hat{s}}_{A} \le t_{0}\), and \(\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) > 0\) for \({\hat{s}}_{A} \ge \max \{t_{1},t_{2}\}\). Since \(\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B})\) is continuous in \({\hat{s}}_{A}\), there is at least one \(c_{A} \in (t_{0},\max \{t_{1},t_{2}\})\), such that \(\Delta (c_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) = 0\). It remains to show the uniqueness of \(c_{A} \in (t_{0},\max \{t_{1},t_{2}\})\), such that \(\Delta (c_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) = 0\). \(\square \)

  1. 1.

    For \({\hat{s}}_{A} > c_{A}\). Let

    $$\begin{aligned} f(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A}) = \mu \left[ 1 - 1_{[{\hat{s}}_{A} \ge t_{1}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} \in {\mathcal {X}}_{B} \vert \mu ) - 1_{[{\hat{s}}_{A} \ge t_{2}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} \notin {\mathcal {X}}_{B} \vert \mu ) \right] \nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
    (32)

    and \(\rho = \xi (0 \vert c_{A}) / \xi (0 \vert {\hat{s}}_{A})\) when \(\mu = 0\). Then,

    $$\begin{aligned} \rho \Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B})&= \rho \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} f(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A}) \xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A}) \text {d} \mu , \end{aligned}$$
    (33)
    $$\begin{aligned}&= \rho \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} f(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A}) \xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A}) \text {d} \mu - \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} f(\mu ,c_{A}) \xi (\mu \vert c_{A}) \text {d} \mu , \end{aligned}$$
    (34)
    $$\begin{aligned}&= \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} f(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A}) \left( \rho - \frac{f(\mu ,c_{A})}{f(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A})} \frac{\xi (\mu \vert c_{A})}{\xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A})} \right) \xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A}) \text {d} \mu . \end{aligned}$$
    (35)

    Given the strict monotone likelihood ratio property, \(\rho > \xi (\mu \vert c_{A}) / \xi (\mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A})\) if and only if \(\mu > 0\). Since \(f(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A})\) is right continuous in \({\hat{s}}_{A}\), there is \(\varepsilon > 0\) such that

    $$\begin{aligned} \rho - \frac{f(\mu ,c_{A})}{f(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A})} \frac{\xi (\mu \vert c_{A})}{\xi ( \mu \vert {\hat{s}}_{A})} > 0 \end{aligned}$$
    (36)

    for \({\hat{s}}_{A} \in (c_{A},c_{A} + \varepsilon )\) if and only if \(\mu > 0\). This, combined with the fact that \(f(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A}) > 0\) if and only if \(\mu > 0\), implies that \(\rho \Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) > 0\) for \({\hat{s}}_{A} \in (c_{A},c_{A} + \varepsilon )\). Since \(\rho > 0\), \(\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) > 0\) for \({\hat{s}}_{A} \in (c_{A},c_{A} + \varepsilon )\).

  2. 2.

    For \({\hat{s}}_{A} < c_{A}\). Use

    $$\begin{aligned} g(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A}) = \mu \left[ 1 - 1_{[{\hat{s}}_{A}> t_{1}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} \in {\mathcal {X}}_{B} \vert \mu ) - 1_{[{\hat{s}}_{A} > t_{2}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} \notin {\mathcal {X}}_{B} \vert \mu ) \right] \nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
    (37)

    instead of \(f(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A})\), because g is left continuous in \({\hat{s}}_{A}\). The steps are identical to 1. Since \(g(\mu ,{\hat{s}}_{A})\) is left continuous in \({\hat{s}}_{A}\), there is \(\varepsilon > 0\) such that \(\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) < 0\) for \({\hat{s}}_{A} \in (c_{A},c_{A} - \varepsilon )\).

Combining the facts that there is a \(c_{A} \in (t_{0},\max \{t_{1},t_{2}\})\), such that \(\Delta (c_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) = 0\), \(\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B})\) is continuous in \({\hat{s}}_{A}\), \(\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) < 0\) for \({\hat{s}}_{A} \le t_{0}\), \(\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) > 0\) for \({\hat{s}}_{A} \ge \max \{t_{1},t_{2}\}\), \(\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) > 0\) for \({\hat{s}}_{A} \in (c_{A},c_{A} + \varepsilon )\), and \(\Delta ({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) < 0\) for \({\hat{s}}_{A} \in (c_{A},c_{A} - \varepsilon )\) implies that \(c_{A} \in (t_{0},\max \{t_{1},t_{2}\})\) is unique. Thus, a unique response function \(R_{A}({\hat{s}}_{A},{\mathcal {X}}_{B}) = 1_{[{\hat{s}}_{A} \ge c_{A}]}\) to consumer B’s strategy \({\mathcal {X}}_{B}\) exists.

Proof of Proposition 3.5

Given Proposition 3.4, consumers A and B’s strategies in a symmetric Bayesian–Nash equilibrium are \({\mathcal {X}}^{*} = \left\{ {\hat{s}} : \chi ({\hat{s}}) = 1_{[{\hat{s}} \ge c^{*}] }\right\} \), where \(c^{*}\) is defined by \(v_{1}(c^{*}) = \beta W(c^{*},{\mathcal {X}}^{*})\). From (7), let

$$\begin{aligned} \Gamma (c)&= v_{1}(c) - \beta W(c,{\mathcal {X}}), \end{aligned}$$
(38)
$$\begin{aligned}&= \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} \mu \xi (\mu \vert c) \text {d} \mu - \beta \max \left\{ 0,\int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} \mu \Phi (S_{B} \ge c \vert \mu ) \xi (\mu \vert c) \text {d} \mu \right\} \nonumber \\&\quad - \beta \max \left\{ 0,\int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} \mu \Phi (S_{B} < c \vert \mu ) \xi (\mu \vert c) \text {d} \mu \right\} , \end{aligned}$$
(39)
$$\begin{aligned}&= \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} \mu \left[ 1 - 1_{[c \ge t_{1}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} \ge c \vert \mu ) - 1_{[c \ge t_{2}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} < c \vert \mu ) \right] \xi (\mu \vert c) \text {d} \mu , \end{aligned}$$
(40)
$$\begin{aligned}&= \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} \mu \left[ 1 - 1_{[ c> t_{1}] } \beta \Phi (S_{B} \ge c \vert \mu ) - 1_{[ c > t_{2}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} < c \vert \mu ) \right] \xi (\mu \vert c) \text {d} \mu , \end{aligned}$$
(41)

where \({\mathcal {X}} = \{{\hat{s}} : \chi ({\hat{s}}) = 1_{[{\hat{s}} \ge c]}\}\). Note that \(\Gamma (c) < 0\) for \(c \le t_{0}\), because \(v_{1}(t_{0}) = 0 < v_{2}(t_{0},s_{B} \ge t_{0})\), and \(\Gamma (c) > 0\) for \(c \ge \max \{t_{1},t_{2}\}\). Since \(\Gamma (c)\) is continuous in c, there is at least one \(c^{*} \in (t_{0},\max \{t_{1},t_{2}\})\), such that \(\Gamma (c^{*}) = 0\). It remains to show the uniqueness of \(c^{*} \in (t_{0},\max \{t_{1},t_{2}\})\), such that \(\Gamma (c^{*}) = 0\). \(\square \)

  1. 1.

    For \(c > c^{*}\). Let \(f(\mu ,c) = \mu \left[ 1 - 1_{[c \ge t_{1}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} \ge c \vert \mu ) - 1_{[c \ge t_{2}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} < c \vert \mu ) \right] \) and \(\rho = \xi (0 \vert c^{*}) / \xi (0 \vert c)\) when \(\mu = 0\). Then

    $$\begin{aligned} \rho \Gamma (c) =&\rho \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} f(\mu ,c) \xi (\mu \vert c) \text {d} \mu = \rho \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} f(\mu ,c) \xi (\mu \vert c) \text {d} \mu \nonumber \\&- \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} f(\mu ,c^{*}) \xi (\mu \vert c^{*}) \text {d} \mu , \end{aligned}$$
    (42)
    $$\begin{aligned} =&\rho \int _{\mu \in {\mathbb {R}}} f(\mu ,c) \left( \rho - \frac{f(\mu ,c^{*})}{f(\mu ,c)} \frac{\xi (\mu \vert c^{*})}{\xi (\mu \vert c)}\right) \xi ( \mu \vert c) \text {d} \mu . \end{aligned}$$
    (43)

    Given the strict monotone likelihood ratio property, \(\rho > \xi ( \mu \vert c^{*}) / \xi ( \mu \vert c)\) if and only if \(\mu > 0\). Since \(f(\mu ,c)\) is right continuous in c, there is \(\varepsilon > 0\) such that

    $$\begin{aligned} \rho - \frac{f(\mu ,c^{*})}{f(\mu ,c)} \frac{\xi (\mu \vert c^{*})}{\xi (\mu \vert c)} > 0 \end{aligned}$$
    (44)

    for \(c \in (c^{*},c^{*} + \varepsilon )\) if and only if \(\mu > 0\). This, combined with the fact that \(f(\mu ,c) > 0\) if and only if \(\mu > 0\), implies that \(\rho \Gamma (c) > 0\) for \(c \in (c^{*},c^{*} + \varepsilon )\). Since \(\rho > 0\), \(\Gamma (c) > 0\) for \(c \in (c^{*},c^{*} + \varepsilon )\).

  2. 2.

    For \(c < c^{*}\). Let \(g(\mu ,c) = \mu \left[ 1 - 1_{[c> t_{1}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} \ge c \vert \mu ) - 1_{[c > t_{2}]} \beta \Phi (S_{B} < c \vert \mu ) \right] \) instead of \(f(\mu ,c)\), because g is left continuous in c. The steps are identical to 1. Since \(g(\mu ,c)\) is left continuous in c, there is \(\varepsilon > 0\) such that \(\Gamma (c) > 0\) for \(c \in (c^{*},c^{*} - \varepsilon )\).

Combining the facts that there is a \(c^{*} \in (t_{0},\max \{t_{1},t_{2}\})\), such that \(\Gamma (c^{*}) = 0\), \(\Gamma (c)\) is continuous in c, \(\Gamma (c) < 0\) for \(c \le t_{0}\), \(\Gamma (c) > 0\) for \(c \ge \max \{t_{1},t_{2}\}\), \(\Gamma (c) > 0\) for \(c \in (c^{*},c^{*} + \varepsilon )\), and \(\Gamma (c) < 0\) for \(c \in (c^{*},c^{*} - \varepsilon )\) implies that \(c^{*} \in (t_{0},\max \{t_{1},t_{2}\})\) is unique.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Santugini, M. On the consumer problem under an informational externality. Econ Theory Bull 8, 149–161 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-019-00174-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40505-019-00174-4

Keywords

JEL Classifications

Navigation