Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Why Wake the Dead? Identity and De-extinction

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I will entertain and reject three arguments which putatively establish that the individuals produced through de-extinction ought to be the same species as the extinct population. Forms of these arguments have appeared previously in restoration ecology. The first is the weakest, the conceptual argument, that de-extinction will not be de-extinction if it does not re-create an extinct species. This is misguided as de-extinction technology is not unified by its aim to re-create extinct species but in its use of the remnants of extinct populations as a resource. The second is the argument from authenticity; the populations produced by de-extinction technologies will be inauthentic if they are not of the extinct species and, therefore, will not be valuable. I argue authenticity is not required in conservation as the value of authenticity varies between people and cultures, and the novelty of de-extinct species will be equally desirable in many cases. The third argument is from retributive justice; we need the de-extinct population to have the same species identity as we owe a moral debt to the extinct population. I find the case for retributive justice unconvincing and argue that acting as if we have a duty to resurrect extinct species will result in a world with less species. Ultimately all the arguments that connect de-extinction technology to species identity fail, leaving us to consider a more complex calculus for the justification of de-extinction in conservation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Higgs’ (2003) view is quite nuanced. This conceptual argument only appears in the larger context of his view, in which restoration projects must consider how to engage local human populations in a relationship with nature. As such, the conceptual argument may be considered instrumental for engaging the public in conservation projects. I recommend reading his book to understand how this conceptual argument sits within his larger ethical framework.

  2. I also believe this is the case for de-extinction but wish to focus on the normative rather than the metaphysical.

  3. For a deft and convincing refutation of Katz’s argument that restoration results in the domination of nature consider Andrew Light’s (2000) discussion. Light argues convincingly that restoration is an important part of environmental practice and addresses Elliot and Katz’s arguments on different grounds to my own.

  4. Some environmental ethicists believe intrinsic value is relational, depending on the agents who value the entity (Elliot 1992; Sandler 2010). If intrinsic value is relational, it is dependent the act of valuation by the relevant agents and ultimately their unique individual psychology. Therefore, my argument still bears on this type of value.

  5. This is based off estimates of human caused extinctions (Ceballos et al. 2015; Sandom et al. 2014). This does not mean we are in a good position to know whether any particular extinction was caused by human action. Instead these are estimates on the data around the difference between background rates of extinction and the rates of extinction when human populations either move into a region or rapidly expand in size. So, while we know extinctions occur, it is difficult to attribute individual extinctions to human actions.

  6. This I will fully admit involves entertaining the idea that we have to do some sort of utility calculation. But many deontologists defend threshold/non-absolutist/moderate forms of deontology duties can be weighed in some sense (Kagan 1998, pp. 79–84).

References

  • Archer, M. (March 2013). Second chance for tasmanian tigers and fantastic frogs. www.ted.com, TEDx DeExtinction. https://www.ted.com/talks/michael_archer_how_we_ll_resurrect_the_gastric_brooding_frog_the_tasmanian_tiger

  • Barnosky, A. D., Matzke, N., Tomiya, S., Wogan, G. O., Swartz, B., Quental, T. B., et al. (2011). Has the Earth/’s sixth mass extinction already arrived? Nature, 471(7336), 51–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bascompte, J., Jordano, P., Melián, C. J., & Olesen, J. M. (2003). The nested assembly of plant–animal mutualistic networks. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 100(16), 9383–9387.

    Google Scholar 

  • Basl, J. (2017). A trilemma for teleological individualism. Synthese, 194(4), 1057–1074.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. R., Maloney, R. F., Steeves, T. E., Brazill-Boast, J., Possingham, H. P., & Seddon, P. J. (2017). Spending limited resources on de-extinction could lead to net biodiversity loss. Nature Ecology & Evolution, 1, 0053.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottrill, M. C., Joseph, L. N., Carwardine, J., Bode, M., Cook, C., Game, E. T., et al. (2008). Is conservation triage just smart decision making? Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 23(12), 649–654.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. (2016). A case for resurrecting lost species—review essay of Beth Shapiro’s, “How to Clone a Mammoth: The Science of De-extinction”. Biology and Philosophy, 31(5), 747–759.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. (2017). On the authenticity of de-extinct organisms, and the genesis argument. Animal Studies Journal, 6(1), 61–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ceballos, G., Ehrlich, P. R., Barnosky, A. D., García, A., Pringle, R. M., & Palmer, T. M. (2015). Accelerated modern human–induced species losses: Entering the sixth mass extinction. Science Advances, 1(5), e1400253.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2014). The ethics of de-extinction. NanoEthics, 8(2), 165–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M., Justus, J., & Regan, H. M. (2010). The natural environment is valuable but not infinitely valuable. Conservation Letters, 3(4), 224–228.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cottrell, S., Jensen, J. L., & Peck, S. L. (2014). Resuscitation and resurrection: The ethics of cloning cheetahs, mammoths, and Neanderthals. Life Sciences, Society and Policy, 10(1), 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Vos, J. M., Joppa, L. N., Gittleman, J. L., Stephens, P. R., & Pimm, S. L. (2015). Estimating the normal background rate of species extinction. Conservation Biology, 29(2), 452–462.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delord, J. (2014). Can we really re-create an extinct species by cloning? A metaphysical analysis. In The ethics of animal re-creation and modification (pp. 22–39). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desjardins, E. (2015). Historicity and ecological restoration. Biology and Philosophy, 30(1), 77–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dortch, J., Cupper, M., Grün, R., Harpley, B., Lee, K., & Field, J. (2016). The timing and cause of megafauna mass deaths at Lancefield Swamp, south-eastern Australia. Quaternary Science Reviews, 145, 161–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliot, R. (1982). Faking nature. Inquiry, 25(1), 81–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliot, R. (1992). Intrinsic value, environmental obligation and naturalness. The Monist, 75(2), 138–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1974). The rights of animals and future generations. In W. Blackstone (Ed.), Philosophy and environmental crisis. Athens: University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2014). What is the value of historical fidelity in restoration? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 45, 97–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2016). Ecological restoration and biodiversity conservation. In J. Garson, A. Plutynski, & S. Sarkar (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of biodiversity (pp. 56–68). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. E. (1992). Green political theory. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greely, H. (2013). De-extinction: Hubris or hope? In TEDx DeExtinction. Washington, DC, TEDx: Grosvenor Auditorium.

  • Higgs, E. (2003). Nature by design: People, natural process, and ecological restoration. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs, R. J., & Cramer, V. A. (2008). Restoration ecology: Interventionist approaches for restoring and maintaining ecosystem function in the face of rapid environmental change. Annual Review of Environment and Resources, 33, 39–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honig, F. (1954). The reparations agreement between Israel and the Federal Republic of Germany. The American Journal of International Law, 48(4), 564. https://doi.org/10.2307/2195023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jebari, K. (2016). Should extinction be forever? Philosophy & Technology, 29(3), 211–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Justus, J., Colyvan, M., Regan, H., & Maguire, L. (2009). Buying into conservation: Intrinsic versus instrumental value. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 24(4), 187–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1998). Normative ethics. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1996 [1797]). The metaphysics of morals. Cambridge University Press Cambridge.

  • Katz, E. (1996). The problem of ecological restoration. Environmental Ethics, 18(2), 222–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, E. (2012). Further adventures in the case against restoration. Environmental Ethics, 34(1), 67–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koch, P. L., & Barnosky, A. D. (2006). Late Quaternary extinctions: State of the debate. Annual Review of Ecology, Evolution, and Systematics, 37.

  • Lean, C., & Sterelny, K. (2016). Ecological hierarchy and biodiversity. In J. Garson, A. Plutynski, & S. Sarkar (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of biodiversity (pp. 56–68). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Light, A. (2000). Ecological restoration and the culture of nature: A pragmatic perspective. In P. Gobster & B. Hull (Eds.), Restoring nature: Perspectives from the social sciences and humanities (pp. 49–70). Washington, DC: Island Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Pettit, P. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maier, D. S. (2012). What’s so good about biodiversity?: A call for better reasoning about nature’s value (Vol. 19). Springer Science & Business Media.

  • Miller, G. H. (2005). Ecosystem collapse in pleistocene Australia and a human role in megafaunal extinction. Science, 309, 287–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minteer, B. A. (2015). The perils of de-extinction. Minding Nature, 8(1), 11–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Saborido, C., & Moreno, A. (2009). An organizational account of biological functions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(4), 813–841.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1983). Abnormal psychobiology. Unpublished Ph.D. Thesis, LaTrobe.

  • Norton, B. (1987). Why preserve natural variety? Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Page, E. A. (2007). Climate change, justice and future generations. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robert, A., Fontaine, C., Veron, S., Monnet, A. C., Legrand, M., Clavel, J., et al. (2017). Fixism and conservation science. Conservation Biology, 31(4), 781–788.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohwer, Y., & Marris, E. (2018). An analysis of potential ethical justifications for mammoth de-extinction and a call for empirical research. Ethics, Policy & Environment, 21(1), 127–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, R. (2010). The value of species and the ethical foundations of assisted colonization. Conservation Biology, 24(2), 424–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, R. (2014). The ethics of reviving long extinct species. Conservation Biology, 28(2), 354–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandom, C., Faurby, S., Sandel, B., & Svenning, J. C. (2014). Global late Quaternary megafauna extinctions linked to humans, not climate change. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 281(1787), 20133254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (2005). Biodiversity and environmental philosophy: An introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (2011). Habitat reconstruction: Moving beyond historical fidelity. Philosophy of ecology (pp. 327–362). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (2012). Environmental philosophy: From theory to practice. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seddon, P. J., Moehrenschlager, A., & Ewen, J. (2014). Reintroducing resurrected species: Selecting DeExtinction candidates. Trends in Ecology & Evolution, 29(3), 140–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, B. (2015). How to clone a mammoth: The science of de-extinction. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, B. (2017). Pathways to de-extinction: How close can we get to resurrection of an extinct species? Functional Ecology, 31(5), 996–1002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherkow, J. S., & Greely, H. T. (2013). What if extinction is not forever? Science, 340(6128), 32–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siipi, H. (2014). Authenticity of animals. In M. Oksanen & H. Siipi (Eds.), The ethics of animal re-creation and modification: Reviving, rewilding, restoring (pp. 22–39). Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siipi, H. (2016). Biodiversity and human-modified entities. In J. Garson, A. Plutynski, & S. Sarkar (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of biodiversity (pp. 125–138). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siipi, H., & Finkelman, L. (2017). The extinction and de-extinction of species. Philosophy & Technology, 1–15.

  • Slater, M. H., & Clatterbuck, H. (2018). A pragmatic approach to the possibility of de-extinction. Biology and Philosophy, 33(1-2), 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Southwood, N. (2016). Does “ought” imply “feasible”? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 44(1), 7–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, H., Dussex, N., & van Heezik, Y. (2017). De-extinction needs consultation. Nature Ecology & Evolution, 1(1), 1–1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, M. G. (2012). The flickering genes of the last mammoths. Molecular Ecology, 21(14), 3379–3381. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1365-294X.2012.05594.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, D. (2014). The restorationist argument for extinction reversal. In M. Oksanen & H. Siipi (Eds.), The ethics of animal re-creation and modification (pp. 40–59). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weston, A. (1985). Beyond intrinsic value: Pragmatism in environmental ethics. Environmental Ethics, 7(4), 321–339.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christopher Hunter Lean.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lean, C.H. Why Wake the Dead? Identity and De-extinction. J Agric Environ Ethics 33, 571–589 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-020-09839-8

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-020-09839-8

Keywords

Navigation