Due to political fragmentation and the weakness of scientific institutions at the beginning of the nineteenth century, Italian natural history scholars took a great interest in the activities of the leading European research centers. This was also the case in Piedmont, a region that had been ruled for centuries by the Savoy dynasty and was historically linked to France by many geographical and cultural ties. Unlike other Italian territories, Piedmont did not become part of the Kingdom of Italy—a vassal state of the Napoleonic Empire—but was instead directly annexed to France and placed under imperial administration. Thus, Paris became both a political point of reference and a privileged scientific pole of attraction for Piedmontese naturalists. Undertaking a challenging journey through the mountains, many scholars moved to the transalpine capital, where they had the opportunity to study museum collections that were far more organized and comprehensive than those available in Italy, as well as to meet leading scientists of the time. This was the path taken by Franco Andrea Bonelli (1784–1830), who distinguished himself as a solid supporter of Lamarck’s theories on the variability of species. In Italy, transformism was widely circulated, though it was not central to scientific debate and was often confined to private reflections (Corsi 1984). Although Bonelli is no exception, as we will see, he nevertheless provides a rare example of the presence of Lamarckian theses in the Italian academic panorama. Bonelli’s anthropological work is another factor that renders him so interesting, testifying to an early responsiveness to European scientific research. These two lines of investigation were inevitably destined to intertwine, providing innovative interpretations of human history.Footnote 1

Bonelli’s Early Years

Franco Andrea Bonelli was the twelfth son of Tommaso and Veronica Boschis. He was born in Cuneo on 10 November 1784, not long before the end of the ancien régime, sealed by the surrender of the Kingdom of Sardinia to the French in December 1798. Coming from a well-off family, Bonelli began his education at the College of the Somascan Fathers in Fossano at the age of ten, before moving to Turin with his father. According to his biographers, in these years his interests centered on mechanics, but this soon gave way to natural history and, in particular, ornithology—perhaps because of the similarity between flying machines and bird wings.Footnote 2

Bonelli began to read the key texts on natural history available to him and to spend time with some of the naturalists working in Turin.Footnote 3 Among them were Michele Spirito Giorna (1741–1809), who had taught zoology and comparative anatomy at the local university since 1802, the anatomist Luigi Rolando (1773–1831), and the physician Giambattista Rubinetti (1776?–1827), an amateur ornithologist and entomologist. Through exchanges and excursions with his friends, Bonelli began to assemble a collection of birds and insects, which was also visibly enriched through his correspondence with Italian and European naturalists.

While ornithology was Bonelli’s first passion, this was followed by entomology, as demonstrated by the twenty-two zoological and six hunting notebooks he drafted in the early nineteenth century. Initially devised as a collection of tips for bird hunting, with a view towards a work Bonelli planned to publish, these notebooks assumed a different character over the years, coming to take the form of an almost daily diary of observations, scientific descriptions, and curiosities, as well as of interesting reflections on taxonomic issues. In these notes—dating from the time Bonelli was between fifteen and twenty years of age—as well as in his correspondence with the Genoese entomologist Massimiliano Spinola (1780–1857), one can detect a number of questions that would leave their mark on all his work. A careful observation of anatomical differences led Bonelli to explore the limits of species and of constant varieties that, in his opinion, were the result of the action of “climate or nourishment.”Footnote 4 No matter how convinced he was of the wisdom of nature and its overall harmony, Bonelli was already sensitive to the question of the variability of species owing to environmental factors. Thus, in the early months of 1807, he noted that the shape of organs seemed to be the consequence of life habits and not vice versa:

The organs seem to be intended for the way of life, not the way of life for the organs; evidence of this can be found in ducks. The wild duck, which spends its life in lakes and rivers, has compressed legs, as do all swimming birds; the legs of the domestic duck, on the contrary, which is forced to live in a farmyard, where it can finds only a little water but not enough to swim in, are almost round. Other parts such as wings, membranes etc. must also be subject to changes. Rarely do we see a domestic duck fly.Footnote 5

Lamarck held similar views on the subject, but examples of adaptive morphological features in birds—often associated with teleological considerations—were also common in other contemporary works. Bonelli was certainly familiar with the Nouveau dictionnaire d’histoire naturelle (1803–1804), one of the great encyclopedic dictionaries published in France, which was edited by Julien-Joseph Virey (1775–1846), a physician and disciple of Buffon. Virey wrote several entries for the dictionary and quoted extensively—albeit critically—from Lamarck’s studies, thus facilitating their circulation.Footnote 6

During this period, Bonelli also looked into a new method of classification, which would move beyond the unsatisfactory chain of beings propounded by Charles Bonnet (1720–1793) and provide a more accurate reflection of the complex interactions among living beings. He, therefore, began to develop alternative representations in the shape of concentric circles or networks.Footnote 7

This youthful apprenticeship took shape in a short publication completed in 1807, entitled Specimen Faunae Subalpinae, in which Bonelli described thirty species of Piedmontese beetles (Bonelli 1812). Shortly afterward, he presented another work on the same subject at the Academy of Sciences in Turin: Observations entomologiques (1811a, 1813). In the meantime, he also wrote a Catalogue des oiseaux du Piémont (1811b), which set out the Latin, French, and Piedmontese nomenclature of over 200 species of birds. These were the only printed works by Bonelli, apart from a few other zoological memoirs; many of his handwritten notes were destined to remain unpublished.

In May 1809, a chair at the Academy of Sciences became vacant upon the death of Michele Spirito Giorna. Thanks to the esteem he had earned through his Observations entomologiques, Bonelli was chosen as Giorna’s successor, thereby becoming a full member of the subalpine scientific elite. In addition, Giorna’s position as Chair of Zoology at the university was open. The distinguished French naturalist Georges Cuvier (1769–1832), an advisor for the Imperial University at the time, was charged with finding a successor. Between 1809 and 1810, Cuvier traveled through Italian departments, inspecting the existing schools and universities to align them with French institutions. In Piedmont, Cuvier found the university to be advanced and efficient, which was the legacy of the “well-administered” Savoyard state.Footnote 8 A few years earlier, Napoleon himself had been impressed by the centralization of the Piedmontese educational system, taking it as a model for reorganizing the entire Imperial University. During his time in Turin in March 1810, Cuvier got to know Bonelli; he was impressed by his work and suggested that he expand his knowledge with a view toward being appointed to the chair of zoology. He invited Bonelli to visit Paris and the Muséum national d’histoire naturelle, which was the hub of European zoological studies at the time, where foremost scholars of the continent would meet.

Anxious to prove himself up to the task, in July 1810 Bonelli left Turin for Paris, where he took courses at the Muséum and continued his research on beetles. This one-year stay in the imperial capital was marked by his final acceptance of the transformist theory, which he would go on to develop and defend throughout his career. A key moment in this process was his meeting with Jean-Baptiste Lamarck (1744–1829), professor of invertebrate zoology, who took an immediate interest in and liking for the young Piedmontese scholar. Bonelli was, in fact, familiar with the Lamarckian theses even before his trip to Paris: the pair could then engage with one other on common ground since they shared the same fundamental ideas on the variability of nature.Footnote 9 Bonelli was one of the twenty-five Italian students of Lamarck and one of the very few to disseminate his ideas in Italy, together with the Neapolitan Giosuè Sangiovanni (1776–1849).Footnote 10

Bonelli and the Transformist Theory: The Letter to Franz Ziegler

Once he had returned to Turin in the autumn of 1811, Bonelli settled into the position of Chair of Zoology, which he occupied until his death in 1830, and began to offer courses that included a considerable focus on transformism. Evidence of his beliefs can be found in his preparatory notes for his lectures and in the handwritten “philosophical” reflections published at the beginning of the twentieth century by the zoologist Lorenzo Camerano (1856–1917).

One particularly interesting source can be found in a letter that Bonelli sent in January 1813 to his colleague Franz Andreas Ziegler (1761–1842), custodian of the Vienna imperial-royal cabinet of natural history. Bonelli had been in contact with Ziegler since 1806, when he was working in the entomological section of the cabinet.Footnote 11 The letter from 1813 is significant; it provides a clear synthesis of Bonelli’s positions, his attitude towards Lamarck, and the anxieties that the support for certain ideas could elicit at the time. Given his ideas on the variability of species, Bonelli highlighted the existence of a link between two beetles, Carabus cyaneus and Carabus coelatus, arguing that the former might have originally been a variety of the latter. Ziegler disagreed and in March 1812 wrote a letter to criticize his colleague’s view. Bonelli returned to the matter a year later, when, to explain this minor question, he broadened the discussion to include a wide overview of his ideas on nature.Footnote 12

At the beginning of his letter, Bonelli unhesitatingly branded the constancy of nature and final causes as “prejudices,” thereby disrupting the Aristotelian legacy that continued to dominate natural history. For him, such convictions were merely the result of religious beliefs that had not been adequately contested or of an almost childish astonishment at the wonders and order of nature. Such order and constancy were merely transitory, such perfection was merely superficial: they were the result of the apparent impossibility of explaining natural phenomena using the tools of science. Therefore, it was necessary to move beyond established opinions and to give due consideration to certain unquestionable facts, such as the differences between the races of human beings, dogs, or other domestic animals. Such variations were not due to captivity itself, but rather to the many combinations of climate, nourishment, and habits.

The way organisms were conditioned by their milieu—the very essence of Lamarck’s theory—could be proved a posteriori by the study of birds, animals Bonelli knew well. Their plan of organization usually consisted of four fingers—three that turned forward as well as a thumb that turned backward to allow them to rest on branches. However, thumbs proved useless in species that lived on the ground or in water; as a matter of fact, they appeared to be less developed and even on the verge of disappearing, as in the genus Charadrius. Bonelli saw this as confirmation of the absence of final causes: a wise nature would have ruled out the thumb completely from the start, while the descending gradation could only be explained by the progressive transformation of living beings according to external circumstances.

An in-depth examination of the nature of such circumstances and how they could have acted on the organism was still required. In general, however, two processes could be observed in nature: a tendency towards perfection or increased complexity and an adaptation of organs to habits according to the theory of use and non-use. While acknowledging Lamarck’s contribution to the study of these phenomena, Bonelli did not hesitate to offer harsh criticism for his excessive speculation:

In his Philosophie zoologique, Mr. Lamarck presented (albeit only after many observations by Pallas, Buffon and many other observational zoologists) germs and a great deal of indirect evidence in favor of such a doctrine. Yet if the author himself had been less a thinker and more a meticulous observer, and if, most importantly, he had gone into the minute details of some aspects of zoology and studied a larger number of animals, he would somehow have avoided certain mistakes and many ridiculous considerations that inflict great damage upon the well-founded observations and considerations with which they are mixed up.Footnote 13

An equivalent for the well-known variations among domestic animals could be found in wild animals and their varieties, which were usually believed to be constant if examined in over a short period of time and under stable circumstances. Furthermore, the ambiguity of the notions of species and variety led zoologists to be overzealous and create a new species for each slight variation. According to Bonelli, who claimed that only individuals existed, the advancement of science would prove traditional taxonomic divisions to be groundless.

Circumstances could vary according to infinite and obscure combinations, even in very narrow spaces, resulting in the most diverse animals; nevertheless, susceptibilité—namely, adaptation to the environment—was just one of two factors involved in the transformation of species. Following Lamarck’s idea of the marche de la nature [march of nature], Bonelli also believed in a tendency towards perfection—named développement—which acted both at the level of the individual and at higher taxonomic levels.Footnote 14 While individual growth was easily detectable, the development of a whole species occurred more slowly, “like a clock sphere that turns every thousand years, and whose motion thus becomes visible and noticeable to us only by comparison made in distant times.”Footnote 15 Such a movement could only be perceived by considering the different degrees of organization of the classes occupying the rungs of the evolutionary ladder.

Lamarck had introduced the notion of pouvoir de la vie [power of life] or marche de la nature in his Recherches sur l’organisation des corps vivans (1802) and supported it with increasing insistence in his later works. Bonelli’s distinction between développement and susceptibilité followed the fundamental lines of Lamarck’s argument but lacked the theoretical support Lamarck found in his physicochemical tenets. Despite his inconsistent statements (which have sparked intense debates on the relative value of the power of life or, rather, the effect of circumstances), scholars agree that in Lamarck’s case, “la cause qui tend sans cesse à composer l’organisation” [the cause that constantly tends to complicate organization] had no vitalistic value.Footnote 16 Far from it; the idea of the power of life was inextricably bound up with the role of circumstances and hinged on the plastic properties of organic movement, a fundamental attribute of vital phenomena.

According to this view, bodily fluids, by forging paths and channels in the organism, could increase its size, complicate its structure, create new organs, and render their functions more specialized.Footnote 17 These movements were closely related to use and disuse, therefore dependent on circumstances, and explained both ontogeny and phylogeny.Footnote 18 The growth of a single organism from the embryonic to the adult state was due to mouvement organique [organic movement], but its repetition over long periods of time, combined with heredity, had also resulted in the gradual complexification of the animal series.Footnote 19 Bonelli placed a strong emphasis on this symmetry, but his analysis proved less refined, given that it lacked any reference to fluid physics and organic movement. As a result, Lamarck’s mechanism and his rejection of vitalistic or teleological principles could also appear to be undermined. While on the one hand Bonelli firmly rejected the idea of final causes, he nonetheless admitted, albeit hypothetically, divine intervention to explain développement or described it as a random phenomenon or unintelligible force.Footnote 20

Lamarck had used the notion of the marche de la nature to account for the increasing complexity that could be noticed when comparing animal classes, the so-called grandes masses [great groups] identified through the study of the main organic systems. Local and varying circumstances explained the external characters of species and the deviations of the animal series.Footnote 21 Bonelli followed this pattern, associating development with the “gradation des êtres et leur enchaînement” [gradations of beings and their connections] and susceptibility with the “branches et la variété” [branches and variety].Footnote 22 For Lamarck, however, the march of nature was not truly autonomous: it was an artifice that was useful for underlining the factual reality of a graduated animal series, but could not be separated from the dynamic of fluids and the relationship between organism and environment. This was the essential mechanism of transformation, which ultimately also explained the increasing complexity of living beings.Footnote 23 Bonelli, on the other hand, seemed to believe in a sharper distinction between the two factors.

This was a real turning point for Bonelli’s views, even more so than for Lamarck’s. Not only did he conjecture that a supernatural intervention might be at work, but he also claimed to have reconciled religion and science through his interpretation of the first factor of transformation. Through a personal exegesis of the Bible, he justified the march of nature through God’s command crescite et multiplicamini: “multiply” was a clear reference to reproduction, while crescite—literally “grow”—must stand for something other than individual growth, since all animals had been created as adults. It was here that Bonelli found a point of contact with his theories, interpreting crescite as an invitation to increase the number of varieties and species, that is, to transform.Footnote 24

Later in his letter to Ziegler, Bonelli avoided the objection that had already been pitted against transformism after the discovery of mummified animals during Napoleon’s Egyptian campaign. Cuvier had indeed found a perfect similarity between mummies and existing animals, which he had taken as the basis for an argument in favor of the fixity of species. As Lamarck had done in Philosophie zoologique (1809, vol. 1, pp. 69–71), Bonelli replied that the elapsed time was too short to produce variations, especially in stable environmental conditions. The mummies found in the Egyptian tombs, however, were humans or animals with an already “perfected” organization, which would therefore not show traces of the natural tendency towards perfection.

Writing with a transformist slant—or even simply expressing such convictions—was imprudent for various reasons, however. Bonelli asked Ziegler to return his letter after reading it carefully and reflecting on its contents. This paved the way for a reflection on social and religious questions, which help explain his caution and the absence of works devoted to a topic that was always at the center of his research. Bonelli believed that early-nineteenth-century Piedmont was not ready to acknowledge and accept such theories, which went beyond the methods with which natural history had been developed up to that point. It would be even less so after the Restoration, just a few months later.

The variability of species was on a collision course with divine creation. Bonelli confessed to Ziegler that he was “intimately convinced of the existence and omnipotence of a God” who had brought the world to life and given beings the faculty to develop. However, he branded the idea of a Supreme Authority that enjoyed creating infinite varieties that were completely similar to each other, except for tiny differences, as “ridiculous and childish.” According to Bonelli, attributing such trifles to the work of a higher will was:

as unworthy of a reasonable man as wishing to still believe that the sun revolves around the earth would be, that all the animals – indistinctly – were in Noah’s Ark, and other similar childish, inconsistent, and foolishly imagined nursery rhymes believed only by those born blind, those lacking any common sense, or by those who at least intend to make no use of it.Footnote 25

Despite his inherent religious convictions, Bonelli was sure that revealing his ideas would lead to accusations of rashness and disbelief, placing him in an uncomfortable position against the social order.

Thus far, we have considered the personal and religious reasons for Bonelli’s silence, but there was also a problem related to scientific method. The continuous, unlimited transformation of nature threatened all the taxonomic efforts carried out by naturalists. These ultimately proved useless, since the natural productions they claimed to define were destined to vary. A transformist zoologist had little interest in a natural history made up only of labels, and Bonelli maintained that he was simply sticking to his principles when he suggested that the Carabus coelatus could be a variety of the cyaneus. A classification that established a barrier between these two beetles while being content to consider every breed of dog as belonging to the same species, even if they differed greatly in appearance, was incongruent.

In short, two very dissimilar ways of approaching the discipline existed: that of the systematic naturalist, who judged animals based on their current anatomical characters (which were accorded a decisive value since they were considered to be stable and real), and that of the philosopher naturalist, who was eager to investigate the changes animals had undergone over the centuries, along with their origin and genealogy. The work of the practical zoologists was, at first sight, useful and coherent, because the two mechanisms of transformation only acted over very long timespans. However, if one reflected on this immense time scale, there was no doubt that their taxonomic systems would prove wrong. Bonelli conceded that a practical naturalist could—and indeed should—take no interest in philosophical issues that would “soon plunge his work into chaos,” depriving him of the reassuring compass provided by so-called constant characters. To a certain extent, to continue to “produce heavy, classic books of natural history,” one had to resign oneself to using traditional methods.

In the final part of his letter to Ziegler, Bonelli proposed another argument, which touched on the field of anthropology. Earlier, Bonelli had pointed out that dogs were all generally considered to belong to the same species, despite their vastly different appearances. He then proceeded to look at the similar case of the human species:

Man, for example, is white here, black in Africa, short in Lapland, tall in Patagonia, and so forth; all such differences are mere bagatelles. Man is one everywhere, and while we judge him so liberally, we count the number of spots on the 24 punctata ladybug and the Tinea evonimella, we observe the different changing shades of a butterfly, we separate the lucanus capreolus from the cervus, we distinguish the hare from the rabbit, the cicindela danubialis from the hibryda etc., etc.Footnote 26

Bonelli was taking a position in the debate on the descent of the human races and standing up for the theory of monogenism, according to which all races shared a common origin. The problem of man’s place in nature remained a focal question in the struggle against evolutionary theories for a long time, up to the Descent of Man (Darwin 1871) and beyond.

The Classification of Man

The remarks Bonelli slipped into his letter to Ziegler, almost in passing, were the result of reflections he had been engaged in over the years, revealing an anthropological interest that was still rare among Italian naturalists. Aware of how sensitive a subject the question of man was, Bonelli overturned it in favor of transformism and used it as a solution to religious concerns.

At the time, the natural history of man was no longer a novelty. Since the middle of the eighteenth century, European naturalists had included human beings—as a species—in the scope of their discipline, classifying them in relation to other animals and in light of the physical differences observed in the various regions of the globe. In their exploration of the boundaries between man and apes, scholars had to reckon with a long tradition of fabulous accounts, pathological cases, and intermediate forms, and the question was closely linked to the understanding of the differences within the human species.Footnote 27 As Duvernay-Bolens (1995) noted, there was a relationship between the place assigned to man in the animal kingdom and the classification of human varieties or races. Between the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, the advocates of two opposing lines of thought confronted each other, namely the monogenists—who believed in a common origin of all men—and the polygenists—who, on the contrary, maintained that distinct stocks and multiple human species existed. An analysis of their positions reveals a correlation between the taxonomic level at which man was placed and his internal subdivisions: the closer man came to apes, the more a disruptive tendency emerged within the human species, which was then divided into multiple races or species. The bitter confrontation between these factions led to the emergence of a “science of races” (Blanckaert 2003), which relegated the question of the origins of man to the background and instead placed the classification of existing groups at the center of attention.Footnote 28 Before delving deeper into Bonelli’s ideas about man, it is worth briefly outlining the main anthropological concepts that had emerged in previous decades.

Carl Linnaeus (1707–1778) claimed that, as a historian following the principles of natural science, he could find no difference between man and monkeys.Footnote 29 In the tenth edition of Systema Naturae, he placed the genus Homo in the mammalian order of primates—alongside Simia, Lemur, and Vespertilio—and divided it into two species: Homo sapiens and Homo troglodytes. Yet Linnaeus was still employing a purely logical-classificatory framework, and this division did not affect his unitary vision of man.Footnote 30

Linnaeus’s solution was contrasted with the fact that man, the only two-handed being, belonged to the distinct and autonomous order Bimana. Georges-Louis Leclerc, count de Buffon (1707–1788) was the first to use this label, while remaining convinced that, as a natural object, man should be described and placed among animals. Anatomically speaking, there was no radical discontinuity, but, as Linnaeus maintained, the dignity of man emerged strongly at the moral and metaphysical levels.Footnote 31 Though Buffon was a convinced monogenist, he introduced a fully genealogical concept of race, distinct from that of variety, into the classification of man. Races were the effect of a process of degeneration from a prototype due to climatic causes and, unlike simple varieties, became constant thanks to a hereditary mechanism.Footnote 32

Other scholars strove to find a correspondence between anatomical characters and human superiority, connecting organic structures and intellectual faculties and thus rooting the exceptionality of man in his physical forms. Among them, one key figure was the Göttingen physician Johann Friedrich Blumenbach (1752–1840), who, in his De generis humani varietate nativa (1795), identified and described the anatomical characters that established an impermeable barrier between man (the only genus and species of the Bimana order) and the rest of the animal kingdom.Footnote 33 Blumenbach argued for the unity of the human species, and his theses were a fundamental theoretical basis for early-nineteenth-century monogenists, including Bonelli. However, as Claude-Olivier Doron (2016) has recently pointed out, the diachronic divide between monogenists and polygenists needs to be relativized, at least when one considers that the concept of race was not necessarily linked to the acceptance of an essentialist pattern and that it was often the monogenist authors, including through the concept of degeneration, who supported racial divisions. Even in Blumenbach’s case, the unity of the species did not imply an absolute identity of forms and was instead structured around a classification of man into five races, which gradually faded into each other and which could be discerned through craniological analysis.Footnote 34 In his model, grounded on the notion of Bildungstrieb, Blumenbach recognized the Caucasian race as the undifferentiated prototype of man, from which the other races had degenerated through a deviation of their life force. His model only described physical differences, however, refusing to correlate them deterministically to a hierarchy of intellectual faculties.Footnote 35

Craniology, the basis of Blumenbach’s work, was first theorized in detail by the Dutch anatomist Petrus Camper (1722–1789). Notwithstanding Blumenbach’s criticism of his technique, Camper exerted a significant influence on anthropological studies, since he identified the facial angle as a tool for measuring differences within the human species. Driven not only by scientific interests but also by artistic and aesthetic ones, Camper was intent on defining the characteristics of ideal beauty and determined the width of the facial angle (a hereditary feature) in various human groups.Footnote 36 The white man was the closest to the ideal of beauty, but he was not its prototype: according to Camper, that ideal had only materialized in classical sculpture. Moreover, although the facial angle of the black races almost matched that of certain apes, he did not intend to establish any link other than of a purely geometrical and aesthetic nature and repeatedly stressed significant anatomical and physiological differences.Footnote 37 Despite later interpretations of his theories, which were soon “disfigured” (Blanckaert 1987), there was no relation between the facial angle and the intellectual and moral faculties of human beings: after all, Camper was a convinced anti-slavery monogenist.

It was Cuvier who argued strongly that the animal organization was the root of inner faculties and that it was necessary to overcome the dualism between the body and soul and to acknowledge a link between anatomical characters and intellectual development. The French naturalist initially refused to place human aptitudes on a scale, but in an article written with his colleague Étienne Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire (1772–1844) in 1795, Cuvier identified a direct connection between the proportions of the head, the size of the brain, and its skills.Footnote 38 The facial angle became a measure of the intelligence and the moral and cultural level of three human races, placed on a descending hierarchical scale. As a result, the black race, which showed the most ape-like traits, was considered to be stuck at a lower level of development.Footnote 39 Thus, beyond his formal statements, and even though he considered man as the only species in the Bimana order, Cuvier came close to a “de facto polygenism” (Blanckaert 2003).

In the early nineteenth century, Lamarck contributed to such anthropological studies and did not hesitate to explain the outstanding nature of human faculties through evolutionary mechanisms. The question of man’s place in classification systems was not immediately related to transformism, but it certainly affected the understanding of man as the center of creation, as well as his origin and connection with animals. Bonelli was of course aware of Lamarck’s ideas, but his anthropological interests also led him to read the major works published between the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. The work that struck him the most was De generis humani varietate nativa by Blumenbach, a polestar for anthropology scholars, but he also paid special attention to Camper’s studies.

Following the classification proposed by Blumenbach in 1795, Bonelli in his university courses listed five human varieties that gradually faded into each other: the Caucasian, the Mongolian, the Negro (or Ethiopian, to use Blumenbach’s definition), the American, and the Malaysian.Footnote 40 The cause of the differentiation of these constant varieties or races could be found in environmental conditions: just as they had caused variations in animals, they had also affected man, at least at an intraspecific level. They had a greater effect on him because man had colonized the entire globe thanks to his ability to acclimatize. One of the most obvious variations was of course skin color and, like Blumenbach, Bonelli analyzed this extensively to determine all the possible variations produced by crossbreeding over successive generations.Footnote 41

Blumenbach clearly stated, against any polygenic hypothesis, that all human varieties belonged to a single species. He had not accorded a properly hierarchical order to his system, limiting himself to assigning aesthetic supremacy to the Caucasian forms and features. Some years later, Bonelli, despite sharing the idea of the superiority of the Caucasian race, which he defined as “la plus parfaite” [the most perfect] or, quoting Blumenbach, as the one with a face “regardé comme le plus beau et le plus agréable” [regarded as the most beautiful and agreeable] took his distance from a position that we can now easily recognize as being steeped in Eurocentrism. After having reaffirmed the identity of all human varieties, Bonelli admitted that it was difficult to establish which was the primordial form, “since the principle of choosing the man of that subspecies that [appears] more beautiful and more regular in its forms and proportions only according to our judgment, is unreasonable.”Footnote 42 What is more, advocating that the Caucasian race was the original one led to the others being considered as a degeneration, whereas, on the contrary, a movement of improvement was at work in nature.

Embracing Blumenbach’s conclusions, during his university lectures Bonelli took a strong position against polygenism, which, at the time, was supported by such influential figures as Julien-Joseph Virey and Jean-Baptiste Bory de Saint-Vincent (1778–1846). Virey conceived of intelligence as a subject that science could explore through its instruments and situated human races within a strongly polygenetic framework. His classification of man was widely circulated, especially thanks to the long entries he wrote for the Nouveau dictionnaire d’histoire naturelle.Footnote 43 Informed by Camper’s method and by the work of the English physician Charles White (1728–1813), Virey proposed that two distinct human species existed, one with white and the other with black skin, which were further divided into races.Footnote 44 Black men, marked by a sharper facial angle and brutish features, were condemned to a lower degree of development, akin to that of apes and infinitely distant from the nobility of the white man.Footnote 45

As with Virey, Bory de Saint-Vincent’s theories began to circulate through a very successful dictionary, the Dictionnaire classique d’histoire naturelle, and included a joint analysis of the physical and intellectual parts of the human being.Footnote 46 Firstly, according to Linnaeus’ principles, Bory explicitly placed man among mammals and denied him a privileged position. Indeed, disagreeing with Buffon, Cuvier, and other naturalists such as Louis Daubenton (1716–1800), who had stressed the anatomical differences between man and apes, Bory placed the genus Orang alongside the genus Man within the Bimana order.Footnote 47 According to Bory, monogenists sought every way possible to demonstrate the unity of the human species so as not to contradict the authority of the Holy Texts, hence their continued attachment to the concept of race.Footnote 48 However, the anatomical analysis revealed strong barriers within mankind, which led Bory to distinguish as many as fifteen different species of men. The Japhetic one, namely that of the Europeans, was the most beautiful in terms of its features, while Hottentots were generally inferior in appearance and intellectual skills and demonstrated the link between the genus Man and the genus Orang.Footnote 49

Thus far we have considered Bonelli’s classification of human races in the context of European anthropology, but what did he think about the synchronic and diachronic relationships between man and other animals? In order to clarify Bonelli’s positions on this sensitive topic, a dual distinction needs to be drawn. First, the differences between his private papers and his university lectures must be identified; and second, his study of the current differences between man and animals needs to be distinguished from his evaluation of their origin.

In his lectures on general zoology as well as in his courses on anthropology, Bonelli placed man in the Bimana order. This choice, which was in line with Buffon, Cuvier, and Lamarck’s ideas, was justified by the study of anatomy. Since a course in natural history could only consider physical aspects, Bonelli did not examine metaphysic or moral faculties, but they nevertheless had an indirect part to play. Drawing on the studies by Blumenbach, Camper, Daubenton, and Samuel Thomas Sömmerring on the position of the occipital hole, Bonelli analyzed man’s distinctive characters in depth. Anthropometry and anatomy unequivocally revealed the differences compared to other animals, including those closest to him. Quadrumans, notwithstanding their evident similarities with man, lacked those characteristics that had allowed thought and intellect to develop at the highest level. Their sensory faculties were much less acute; their hands—albeit in possession of opposable thumbs—were less ductile, and their ability to stand had been greatly exaggerated.

The conclusion drawn from the sum of these observations was clear: there were crucial differences between man and apes that fully legitimized the existence of the Bimana order. Indeed, Bonelli made the following statement at the beginning of his discussion, before adding the details we have briefly recalled:

Man by himself forms a species, a genus, an order isolated and distinct from all others, not only because of his moral faculties, but also because of some physical characters deriving from the conformation of his parts, which present the most complete, harmonic, univocal, and, finally, the most perfect combination in all respects.Footnote 50

In light of this, man needed to be thankful to the Author of the universe, who had provided chaos with the power to differentiate and had allowed him to overtake every other animal.Footnote 51 However, even at a superficial glance, a certain similarity undeniably existed between man and the great apes, which had prompted comparisons and analogies. In his lectures, Bonelli reserved a harsh judgment for these hypotheses, rejecting them unequivocally:

In our times, attempts have been made to find the relationships that make the ape species so similar to that of man, to find the analogy, in a word, to justify an attempt to establish a comparison between their respective organization and faculties. This idea – which is very old and which perhaps tended less to elevate man to the level that the author of nature assigned him, than to degrade him by elevating anthropomorphic animals to his level, coarse caricatures of his aspect – this idea, I say, has focused attention on several characters to which attention had not yet been paid, but which were later recognized as being of such importance, that even without these two sublime faculties – reasoning and speech – man would still be eminently distinguished and placed, without comparison, at an infinitely higher rank than apes by the sole consideration of his physical aspect.Footnote 52

Apes were therefore relegated to the condition of “coarse caricatures” of man, but, if nothing else, the debate had the merit of stimulating new anatomical research that led to a reaffirmation of the radical otherness of man.

This comparative analysis demonstrated an unbridgeable gap that set man in a distinct, privileged position compared to other living beings. This could hold true if one remained in the sphere of natural history, avoiding the interference of morals or theology. Such a conclusion, however, was also a source of reassurance at the religious level, and Bonelli was particularly eager to reconcile science and faith. Furthermore, theses of this nature were also in keeping with the conservative atmosphere that prevailed over Piedmont after the Restoration.

The Origin and History of Man

Bonelli was interested in studying man not only for purely descriptive purposes, but also from a historical perspective, investigating the processes that had led human beings to hold a position of supremacy. One of the murkiest questions to be examined was that of the origin of intellectual faculties in man and animals. It was on this point that Bonelli dwelled in the earliest surviving testimony of his reflections on mankind. In March 1803, he noted an interesting reflection in one of his zoological notebooks:

I think that naturalists have taken into consideration characters that are too doubtful to distinguish man from animals. They have said that man thinks, reasons, speaks. All this is worthless. First of all, man thinks. What is it to think? Is it a faculty peculiar to man? Is it a faculty dependent on his power over all other animals?Footnote 53

The ability to think, Bonelli claimed, could not be said to be exclusive to man. Animals, too, showed a form of memory, which was precisely what constituted the core of thought. As for the ability to speak, it was evident in animals such as birds, whose faculties were in a certain sense even better than those of man, since singing allowed them to be heard and understood at great distances.

Bonelli returned to the topic of human and animal intellectual skills repeatedly, pointing out that, if there was a difference, it was a difference in degree and not in substance. In the notes entitled Essai sur les facultés intellectuelles des animaux et sur l’origine de celles de l’homme, written between 1812 and 1814 (Camerano 1908b, pp. 24–29), Bonelli presented various examples that confirmed animals’ ability to think. He also identified the sources of their moral faculties, which included instinct, experience, and the so-called aptitude organique (i.e., an anatomical structure that could be more or less favorable to processing thought). This “organic aptitude” could not be evaluated by taking man’s physical organization as a parameter of perfection: the intellectual system of birds seemed to surpass that of mammals, although their development of corresponding faculties was restricted by other factors, such as their lack of hands. From his observations, Bonelli concluded that reasoning was by no means an essential characteristic of man: all animals would likely have developed such a capacity in favorable circumstances. Like the organs of the body, therefore, even intellectual faculties were subject to a Lamarckian process of improvement.

In those years, Lamarck had also expressed similar positions, arguing that before reaching its current level of perfection, human intelligence may have emerged gradually. Since the Recherches sur l’organisation des corps vivans, he had pointed out a progression, not only in the organization of animals, but also in their communication skills and intelligence. Even men, who were usually the only beings to be attributed with the faculty of reason, displayed an analogous gradation, leading from a Newton or a Voltaire to the most ignorant and prejudiced individuals, who made little use of their intelligence. Like other organs, the brain—the organ of thought—could also develop its skills through continuous exercise. According to Lamarck, the remarkable divide in intelligence between man and animals could be explained by the living conditions of the latter, which simply repeated standard actions to meet their needs. There was a link between physical organization and intellect, and anatomy could have fostered the development of human faculties. Man, the only genus and species in his order, was clearly distinguished from the nearby quadrumans from his vertical station, the position of the occipital hole, and his finger mobility.Footnote 54

So, if the differences were only at the organizational level, why not deduce that they had evolved progressively from the lower forms? Lamarck thus introduced the hypothesis of a genealogical link between man and apes. Shortly afterwards, he described the process of hominization of a chimpanzee. Lamarck’s use of the interrogative form and the future tense when dealing with these problems has raised questions about the true nature of his argument (Stoczkowski 1997), which is nonetheless consistent with his beliefs about the variability of living beings.Footnote 55

A few years later, Lamarck took up the issue again in Philosophie zoologique, where he set out a detailed reconstruction of the process by which a species of quadrumans could evolve, becoming two-handed,Footnote 56 and demonstrated how language and intellectual faculties were refined as a consequence of social life and the need to communicate complex concepts. Nevertheless, he remained cautious, presenting his explanation as a simple hypothesis, which would only have applied if man differed from other animals solely in physical respects and not also in terms of inner faculties. However, the second volume of the work confirmed Lamarck’s convictions and further emphasized the origin of intelligence and spirituality through purely physical mechanisms.Footnote 57

As for Bonelli, some significant passages in his papers prove his belief that the mechanisms of transformation were not just an explanation of the anatomy of living beings; they also came into play with factors that were unrelated to physical organization, such as morals, the progress of civilization, and political systems.Footnote 58 Bonelli’s ideas on the development of human faculties as a result of a process of improvement that also affected animals have been highlighted. To fully understand his views, however, it is also instructive to compare the statements in his university courses with private writings that had no editorial or educational purpose.

The lecture notes previously analyzed date from 1811 and 1813. Meanwhile, Bonelli reflected on transformism and focused on the issue of man, intending to write a book. The two-factor Lamarckian process of transformation also needed to be applied to the human species, which had developed “à la manière des animaux et des plantes” [in the same manner as animals and plants]. Man’s supremacy was the consequence of a successful combination of influential circumstances: if they had been more or less abundant, they would have produced an even more perfect being or, vice-versa, an animal like the ape. Similar mechanisms had generated elephants, hippos, whales, and parrots, which, like man, differed from the other species belonging to their orders. Naturalists could also have established special and distinct orders for them, therefore, including species as close to each other as the varieties of man.

If “rien n’a été réellement créé tel que nous le voyons” [nothing has actually been created as we see it], and if all living beings were equally affected by Lamarckian laws, then man could not be deemed to be the only exception, nor could he be taken as the outcome of a special creation: “In good philosophy we cannot acknowledge a specific creation for man, nor conditions different from those that accompanied the formation of the other inferior animals.”Footnote 59 The study of human origins and evolution therefore overshadowed man’s uniqueness and instead underlined the reasons for his affinity with animals. The effect was an unavoidable downsizing of human ambition and anthropocentrism.

A true philosopher, impartial in his judgment of the entire mass of animals, must recognize that he alone, compared to the universe of which he believes he is the master, or at least the agent and main object, is nothing but dust, as the Holy Scripture says. It was only his pride that led him to believe the contrary. As currently observed in geology and zoology, and our knowledge about fossils, the globe existed long before man, and even all fossil animals are of earlier formation, since no human fossils have been found.Footnote 60

Man was thus regarded merely as one living being among others, and his place in nature was relativized. The excavation of fossil deposits, which was flourishing thanks to the research of Cuvier and Alexandre Brongniart (1770–1847), seemed to demonstrate the complete absence of human remains in the deeper geological strata. According to the Genesis narrative—still widely influential, albeit no longer interpreted literally—the creation of man had taken place at the origin of the world, preceded only slightly by that of animals. Paleontology instead suggested the existence of an extremely ancient pre-human world, which called into question man’s role as the cornerstone of creation.

Bonelli did not intend to deny the superiority of man and his dominance over other animals; rather, he wished to reconsider the causes of these facts in the light of a transformist approach. It should first be noted that, beyond the effects of the two marches of nature, new characters often appeared because of accidental variations. They were then preserved and transmitted hereditarily only in the absence of crossbreeding with individuals that did not possess them. This mechanism explained, on one hand, the perfection of man and his belonging to a single species and, on the other, the impossibility of animals reaching this level and the increasing number of animal species.

Among wild animals, mating occurred freely, while human laws generally forbade marriages between kinsmen. This social convention led to a continuous crossing of different families and the inevitable elimination of accidental variations. Man was therefore affected only by the slow and continuous action of développement and by the conditioning of local circumstances. Environmental factors certainly rendered human races dynamic and modifiable, but, due to the great distances between one climatic zone and another, crossbreeding between different varieties was rare. As such, the individual characteristics of each race were maintained and their peculiarities increased. However, all races were bound by intermediate rings because of the gradual transitions from one climate to another, which thus preserved their unity.

Once accidental variations had been discarded, the effect of the tendency towards perfection could freely develop, widening the gap with animals evermore. In the latter, the sum of accidental variations slowed down development: instead of a “vertical” improvement, a “horizontal” multiplication of the number of races and species occurred. Yet man himself was a factor—and one of no little importance—that conditioned the perfection of animals. As soon as he had “taken up the scepter of the world,” he had acted, in all respects, as a brake on animal développement. His disruptive influence—by altering natural balances, hunting, transferring species to unsuitable regions, and destroying communities—had hindered animal life and the exercise of those functions that could produce a greater perfection. The gap between man, apes, and other animals was thus destined to grow ever wider.

Confirming his interest in social issues, Bonelli compared these phenomena to what happened when an ideal republican order was subverted. Whenever an individual favored by circumstances was able to prevail over others, his superiority was destined to increase with time. A typical case was that of the founder of a dynasty: after initially acting as primus inter pares [first among equals], he then proceeded to gain more and more control over the rest of his fellow citizens, thanks to his weapons or talent, stifling their ambitions to challenge his authority.Footnote 61

When he was younger, Bonelli had believed in a harmonious model of the economy of nature, in which man, animals, plants, and minerals occupied a necessary and mutually useful place, preserving an ecological balance that testified to the wisdom of nature. Now that picture appeared to be called into question by man himself, the most outstanding living being on the physical and moral level. Bonelli was clearly recalling some of the passages from Philosophie zoologique, where Lamarck had sharply underlined man’s part in the destruction of the ecosystem (1809, vol. 1, pp. 351–352). In his work, Lamarck bluntly stated that man was nothing more than a perfected quadruman, thus admitting a close relationship between man and apes. Bonelli, on the other hand, despite approaching a similar position, never took it to its extreme consequences. He avoided confronting the issue directly on several occasions, instead vigorously claiming a form of uniqueness for the human species.

Finding a Solution: Transformism Applied to Anthropology

By situating man within the framework of the process of transformation and improvement common to all living beings, Bonelli’s handwritten papers suggest the hypothesis of a relationship. As a result both of his religious beliefs and the social implications he had raised in his letter to Ziegler, he was unable to take the final step along this dangerous path. In 1818, during the Restoration, he spoke bluntly during his university lectures: despite the lack of human fossil remains, man was “an ancient product of nature, according to a plan established since the origin of the world, towards which every other being of later formation still tends, without ever being able to reach it.” Bonelli thus reaffirmed the gap between man and apes, which had become unbridgeable because some characters had not evolved at the right time. Moreover, man was the most perfect being, “the only one made in the likeness of God: the ape is just the summit of the animal branch directed towards man, modeled on the plan of his organization, such that I shall never take the view that the origin of man can be attributed to a perfected ape.”Footnote 62

Despite some hesitations, doubts, and reversals, however, Bonelli saw the natural history of man as a decisive tool in the defense of transformism. In the conclusion to his letter to Ziegler and elsewhere in his papers, Bonelli presented man as an example of the inconsistency that reigned among classifications. Naturalists considered the differences between human varieties to be negligible, while they employed much stricter criteria to evaluate animal characters and to create new species based on modifications that could be reduced to simple intraspecific variations. Thanks to this repeated observation, during the Restoration period Bonelli developed an argument to respond to the accusations of atheism and betrayal of the Holy Texts that had been tormenting him for a long time.

After 1814, the reinstatement of the Savoy monarchy and the Church’s interference in every sector of society encouraged Bonelli to seek conciliation between transformism and religion. Such concerns are evident in some of his writings that are dedicated to the problem of the “overflowing multiplication of species in natural history.” Reflecting on a taxonomic system that could replace the chain of beings, Bonelli suggested the image of an intricate ramification. Such a structure raised a further question: should branch bifurcations be considered as unchanging or should a diachronic factor be introduced that would give genealogical depth to an ever-changing tree? The answer was obviously the latter and, to justify this idea, Bonelli called man into question.

Fixism, along with strict compliance to traditional taxonomic methods, presented a “very serious inconvenience, disreputable to the decorum of the common origin of the human species transmitted to us by the Holy Scriptures,” because it could lead to an endorsement of polygenic theoriesFootnote 63:

Physically speaking, the differences between the main varieties of man, and often also between subordinate ones, are of much greater consequence and importance than those that occur between one animal and another, one plant and another, belonging to what are usually called true species.Footnote 64

To safeguard the unity of the human species since its outset, as handed down in the Book of Genesis, the only solution was to accept in all beings “a certain variability, inconstancy, versatility, tendency to change or to vary in consequence and direction of the influence of physical circumstances.” In the case of man, Bonelli examined this variability in intraspecific terms, but he had at times considered it from such a perspective as to configure a genealogical link with other animals. Nature’s predisposition to variation was necessarily unlimited—since “the Supreme Creator” had placed no limit on his “double command, crescite et multiplicamini”—and this was therefore the basic premise underpinning any transformist explanation.

Bonelli believed his interpretation of that divine order was completely legitimate because the Scriptures specified neither the number nor the qualities of the animals at the time of creation. However, since they had appeared before Adam, their creation should have occurred in a circumscribed setting and organisms should have been in harmony with local circumstances. God’s command explained their migration instinct and the subsequent multiplication of their species. As such, original creation already included the guidelines for subsequent development, according to a course laid out by the Supreme Wisdom.

Such a solution, Bonelli noted, was “in line with Christian belief.” It could satisfy both religion and science and answer questions that, if left ambiguous, would have compromised the solidity of morals.Footnote 65 Transformism thus drew its strength and raison d’être precisely from the issue of man, which, instead of being the greatest obstacle, became its backbone.

Bonelli’s interest in the history of species—the hallmark of his entire activity—thus went hand in hand with sensitivity to anthropological issues still uncommon in Italy at the time. In both cases, his reflections did not circulate outside the peripheral milieu of Turin, and often even within it, and they failed to have any significant impact on the scientific community. After Bonelli’s death, Lamarckian research, except for some scholars who worked on it privately, suffered a phase of stagnation, if not of genuine ostracism, even in Piedmont, only to reappear in 1848.Footnote 66 The situation was no better for anthropology. When, in 1857, Giustiniano Nicolucci (1819–1904), the Italian founder of the discipline, published Delle razze umane [On the Human Races] (1857–58), he regretted the lack of consideration accorded to those studies in the peninsula. The questions Bonelli had asked himself almost half a century before would, however, remain highly relevant for a long time to come.