Skip to main content
Log in

Does proper function come in degrees?

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Natural selection comes in degrees. Some biological traits are subjected to stronger selective force than others, selection on particular traits waxes and wanes over time, and some groups can only undergo an attenuated kind of selective process. This has downstream consequences for any notions that are standardly treated as binary but depend on natural selection. For instance, the proper function of a biological structure can be defined as what caused that (type of) structure to be retained by natural selection in the past. We usually think of proper functions in binary terms: storing bile is a function of the gall bladder, but making stones is not. However, if functions arise through natural selection, and natural selection comes in degrees, then a binary approach to proper functions is in tension with the biological facts. In order to resolve this tension, we need to revise our standard accounts of proper function. In particular, we may have to seriously consider the possibility that functions themselves come in degrees, in spite of the ramifications this will have for the way we speak about functions and related concepts such as dysfunction, disease, and teleosemantic content.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. And here I am only considering selected effects accounts that concern the influence of past selection in maintaining a trait as it currently manifests, rather than earlier “etiological” accounts which concern the selective history that explains the very origin of the trait (Godfrey-Smith 1994; Griffiths 1993).

  2. As Nicholas Shea puts it: in order to make the notion of representation less mysterious, an account of that representation needs to be in terms that are “non-semantic, non-mental and non-normative” (2013, 497).

  3. Thanks to Stewart Saunders for bringing this example to my attention.

  4. Much of what I say here owes a great deal to discussions with Justine Kingsbury. Additionally, a reviewer for this journal pointed out that the selective story regarding these properties may have recently reversed—minor defects in eye shape can now be medically managed or mitigated with glasses, while selection on sclera color is likely to have remained.

  5. This example has played a notable role in past discussion of functions (e.g. Boorse 2002, 99–101). For various reasons I will use the standard peppered moth story as recounted in the relevant previous literature. However, the details of this case are more complex and ambiguous than usually described, both biologically and methodologically (Cook and Saccheri 2013). Thanks to Sam Woolley for pointing this out.

  6. I don’t necessarily want to insist that this counterexample is completely successful, as I’m not so certain function talk is inappropriate here, and don’t want to place too much stock in unclear intuitions. The important point from our perspective is Garson’s response.

  7. Apparently neurons do compete with one another for survival during brain remodelling in a way that could meet this requirement (Garson 2017, 538).

  8. In a recent article working within a quite different account of functions, Justin Garson and Gualtiero Piccinini suggest that a non-negligible level of contribution to survival or fitness is required in order for some effect to qualify as a function (Garson and Piccinini 2014, 6–7). This would exclude properties that underwent positive selection extremely rarely, but within this context at least, would still admit a great many cases, depending on how one defined “negligible”.

  9. Of course there may be all sorts of pragmatic reasons to impose thresholds on graded attributes, in the same way we might consider someone’s eighteenth birthday an important marker for the purposes of law. However, to use such a fix in this context would be tantamount to admitting that proper functions are a matter of human stipulation, and so once again lose much of what made the notion attractive in the first place.

  10. Although see (Griffiths 1993, p. 419) and (Kingsbury 1999, p. 38–39).

  11. Some non-functional effects may still remain. As Colin Klein pointed out to me, there would still need to be adequate variation in these traits, and in as much as they are forced side-effects of other selected traits, such variation won’t obtain. For example, if there are are no heart valve variants which are both effective and quiet, this selective story won’t obtain. Nevertheless, there will still be hugely many partial functions in the world if we adopt this graded view.

  12. Nicholas Shea has addressed the idea that certain circumstances might cause the relevant functions to be “marginal”, although for different reasons than those discussed here. He considers these to be cases where the representational content is “genuine”, but of potentially reduced explanatory relevance (Shea 2018, 65). Many thanks to a reviewer for this journal for bringing this to my attention.

References

  • Ariew A, Perlman M (2002) Introduction. In: Ariew A, Cummins R, Perlman M (eds) Functions: new essays in philosophy of psychology and biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1-4

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow J, Pargetter R (1987) Functions. J Philos 84(4):181–196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse C (2002) A rebuttal on functions. In: Ariew A, Cummins R, Perlman M (eds) Functions: new essays in philosophy of psychology and biology. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 63–112

    Google Scholar 

  • Changizi M, Weber R, Kotecha R, Palazzo J (2011) Are wet-induced wrinkled fingers primate rain treads? Brain Behav Evol 77(4):286–290

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook L, Saccheri I (2013) The peppered moth and industrial melanism: evolution of a natural selection case study. Heredity 110(3):207–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins R (1975) Functional analysis. J Philos 72:741–765

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson J (2017) A generalized selected effects theory of function. Philos Sci 84(3):523–543

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson J (2019) What biological functions are and why they matter. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garson J, Piccinini G (2014) Functions must be performed at appropriate rates in appropriate situations. Br J Philos Sci 65:1–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1993) Functions: consensus without unity. Pac Philos Q 74(3):196–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1994) A modern history theory of functions. Noûs 28(3):344–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goode R, Griffiths PE (1995) The misuse of Sober’s selection for/selection of distinction. Biol Philos 10(1):99–108

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (1993) Functional analysis and proper functions. Br J Philos Sci 44(3):409–422

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (2009) In what sense does ‘nothing in biology make sense except in the light of evolution’? Acta Biotheor 57(1–2):11–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingsbury J (2006) A proper understanding of Millikan. Acta Analytica 21(3):23–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingsbury J (2008) Learning and selection. Biol Philos 23(4):493–507

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langton S (2010) Gaze perception and visually mediated attention. In: Adams RB, Ambady N, Nakayama K, Shimojo S (eds) The science of social vision. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 108–132

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson J (2015) Defining paradigm Darwinian populations. Philos Sci 82:178–197

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson J, Griffiths PE (2017) Biological criteria of disease: four ways of going wrong. J Med Philos 42(4):447–466

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McBrien NA, Gentle A (2003) Role of the Sclera in the development and pathological complications of Myopia. Prog Retin Eye Res 22(3):307–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (1984) Language, thought, and other biological categories: new foundations for realism. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (1989a) In defense of proper functions. Philos Sci 56:288–302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (1989b) Biosemantics. J Philos 86(6):281–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R (2009) Populations as individuals. Biol Theory 4:267–273

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R (2010) The concepts of population and metapopulation in evolutionary biology and ecology. In: Futuyma DJ, Bell MA, Eanes WF, Levinton JS (eds) Evolution since Darwin: the first 150 years. Sinauer, Sunderland, pp 61–86

    Google Scholar 

  • Millstein R (2015) Thinking about populations and races in time. Stud Hist Philos Sci Part C 52(August):5–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy D (2015) Concepts of disease and health. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (1983) Abnormal psychobiology. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Bundoora, Australia: La Trobe University.

  • Neander K (1991) Functions as selected effects: the conceptual analyst’s defense. Philos Sci 58:168–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau D (1987) Reality and representation. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, PH (2007) Defining dysfunction: natural selection, design, and drawing a line. Philoso Sci 74(3): 364–85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwab J-A, Zenkel M (1998) Filtration of particulates in the human nose. Laryngoscope 108(1):120–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2013) Naturalising representational content. Philos Compass 8(5):496–509

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2018) Representation in cognitive science. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield J (1992) The concept of mental disorder: on the boundary between biological facts and social values. Am Psychol 47(3):373–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield J (2003) Dysfunction as a factual component of disorder. Behav Res Ther 41:969–990

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Welsh MJ, Smith AE (1993) Molecular mechanisms of CFTR chloride channel dysfunction in cystic fibrosis. Cell 73(7):1251–1254

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This work was supported by the Marsden Fund of New Zealand, Fast-Start Grant number 18-MAU-063. Correspondence and comments from Justine Kingsbury were particularly important throughout the development of this article. I also acknowledge extremely useful feedback from two anonymous referees for this journal and audiences at: the Australian National University PhilSoc seminar, the Portland philosophy of science seminar series, the Australasian Association of Philosophy’18 meeting, the ISHPSSB’19 meeting, and the University of Auckland philosophy of biology reading group. Many thanks to everyone.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Matthewson.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Matthewson, J. Does proper function come in degrees?. Biol Philos 35, 39 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-09758-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-020-09758-y

Keywords

Navigation