Skip to main content
Log in

Neither superorganisms nor mere species aggregates: Charles Elton’s sociological analogies and his moderate holism about ecological communities

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper analyzes community ecologist Charles Elton’s ideas on animal communities, and situates them with respect to the classical opposition between organicist–holistic and individualistic–reductionist ecological views drawn by many historians of ecology. It is argued that Elton espoused a moderate ecological holism, which drew a middle way between the stricter ecological holism advocated by organicist ecologists and the merely aggregationist views advocated by some of their opponents. It is also argued that Elton’s moderate ecological holism resonated with his preference for analogies between ecological communities and human societies over more common ones between communities and individual organisms. I discuss, on the one hand, how the functionalist-interactionist approach to community ecology introduced by Elton entailed a view of ecological communities as more or less self-maintaining functionally organized wholes, and how his ideas on this matter were incorporated into their views by organicist ecologists Frederic Clements, Victor Shelford, and Warder C. Allee et al. On the other hand, I identify some important divergences between Elton’s ecological ideas and those of organicist ecologists. Specifically, I show (1) how Elton’s ideas on species distribution, animal migrations, and ecological succession entailed a view of animal communities as exhibiting a weaker degree of part-whole integration than that attributed to them by Clements and Shelford; and (2) how Elton’s mixed stance on the balance of nature idea and his associated views on community stability attributed to communities a weaker form of self-regulation than that attributed to them by Allee et al.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is noteworthy that the two most detailed treatments of Elton’s ideas on communities (and his related ideas on population regulation) are found in unpublished doctoral dissertations (i.e., Cox 1979; Haak 2000). The below discussion owes a lot to those treatments, as well as to the more succinct ones offered by McIntosh (1985), Sheail (1987), and Hagen (1992).

  2. For Elton’s own account of how he was brought to this shift, see Elton and Miller (1954, pp. 461–462).

  3. As pointed out to me by Kurt Jax, an exception to this general observation is Karl August Möbius (1825–1908), whose picture of ecological communities closely anticipates Elton’s functionalist and interactionist picture. Möbius is best known for his work on oyster banks (Möbius 1883), where he introduced the term “biocenosis” to denote ecological communities. On Möbius’s ideas on ecological communities, see Glaubrecht (2008, pp. 17–18), van der Valk (2017, pp. 115–116), Schwarz and Jax (2011, pp. 242–244), and Potthast (this issue).

  4. For detailed discussions of this earlier classificatory and habitat-focused approach, see Griesemer (1990) and Neumann (2017).

  5. For a detailed history of ideas on food chains and food webs, see Egerton (2007).

  6. The Matamek conference gathered scientists from various fields and was organized by wealthy fisheries trader and nature lover Copley Amory on his private estate (for report and proceedings, see Huntington 1932).

  7. For historical discussions of the niche concept, see Cox (1979, Chapter 4), Schoener (1989), Griesemer (1992), Leibold (1995), and Pocheville (2015).

  8. In this respect, Elton’s niche somewhat anticipated the concept of niche construction (Odling-Smee et al. 2003). Elton, however, in contrast to niche construction theorists, seems to have conceived the niche not so much as what is constructed by organisms (the result of construction), but rather as the constructing activity itself.

  9. A most likely inspiration for Elton’s parallels between animal communities and human societies is sociologist Alexander Carr-Saunders (1886–1966), who, together with Julian Huxley, is considered to have acted as his mentor at Oxford. In the preface of his Animal Ecology, Elton explicitly links his understanding of ecology as “the sociology and economics of animals” to Carr-Saunders’s (1922) study of the “sociology and economics” of humans (Elton 1927, p. vii). On the relationship between Elton and Carr-Saunders, see Sheail (1987, p. 90), Hagen (1992, pp. 56–57), and Anker (2001, Chapter 3). For general discussions of functionalism in sociology, see, e.g., Munch (1976) and Moore (1978).

  10. For detailed discussions of Elton’s ideas on animal communities, see Cox (1979, pp. 51–54, Chapter 3) and Hagen (1992, pp. 51–62).

  11. Interestingly, Elton’s ideas, in this respect, aligned with those of Carr-Saunders, who criticized strict Malthusian views on population regulation (see Carr-Saunders 1922, Chapter 9; and for discussions, see Sheail 1987, p. 90; Angner 2009, p. 81). It should be noted, however, that, in later publications (Elton 1958, p. 131), Elton recognized a more important regulative role to intraspecific competition (see Haak 2000, p. 30). For general discussions of Elton’s ideas on population regulation, see Cox (1979, pp. 50–64), Sheail (1987, sec. 2.5.2), Hagen (1992, pp. 56–60), and Haak (2000, pp. 26–30, 43–44).

  12. Elton restated this idea in later publications (e.g., Elton and Miller 1954, p. 463). The distinction between autecology and synecology invoked by Elton in the latter passage was from Swiss ecologists Schröter and Kirchner (1902) and draws a contrast between ecological studies focusing on single species in relation to their environment (autecology) and studies concerned with ecological communities as a whole (synecology). Elton presumably took this distinction from his Oxford colleague Tansley (1923, p. 20).

  13. For historical discussions of organicist views in early ecology, see Bodenheimer (1957), Acot (1987), McIntosh (1998), and Bergandi (1999).

  14. Additional indirect support may be found in the fact that the idea of communities as superorganisms was espoused by Elton’s mentor Julian Huxley, along with novelist H. G. Wells, in the ecology chapter of their book The Science of Life, a huge book that surveyed life sciences for a popular audience. In this book, Wells and Huxley asserted that “it is not altogether fanciful to compare all [the world’s] various [ecological] communities, each one to a sort of super-organism, and in practice much of the thought and work of the ecologist involves that idea” (Wells et al. 1931, p. 578). According to historian of ecology Anker (2001, p. 112), Wells et al.’s chapter on ecology was entirely reviewed by Elton prior to its publication.

  15. For further discussions of Clements’s ideas on ecological succession, see Whittaker (1974), McIntosh (1980, 1985, pp. 76–82), Hagen (1988, 1992, Chapter 2), and Eliot (2007, 2011).

  16. The concept of homeostasis was coined by Cannon (1932) and denoted organisms’ characteristic ability to maintain their state in response to external perturbations. It was inspired by the work of the French physiologist Bernard (1879).

  17. The “quasi-organism” notion alluded to here was from plant ecologist Tansley (1920, 1935).

  18. Elton and Tansley and are known to have been in relatively close contact with each other (see Anker 2001, Chapter 3). Moreover, Elton’s Animal Ecology cites two books by Tansley, and the discussion of ecological succession in chapter 3 of that book draws heavily on Tansley’s works. Hence, I take it that Elton was likely aware of Tansley’s remarks on the organicist analogy.

  19. For discussions of this aspect of Clements and Shelford’s ecology, see Whittaker (1957, pp. 197–198), and Kirchhoff (this issue).

  20. On Clements’s Lamarckianism, see Hagen (1983).

  21. In the interest of not misrepresenting Gleason’s ideas, it must be remarked that, despite his emphasis on contingency, he did not deny that species interactions were important factors in the organization of communities. He regarded interactions between species as important determinants of their ability to establish and maintain themselves in particular locations. Hence, although, for him, the composition of communities was largely contingent, communities nonetheless remained, to a significant extent, interactive systems. His views, in this respect, were very close to those I am attributing to Elton. On Gleason’s ecological ideas, see McIntosh (1975, 1995), Nicolson (1990), and Nicolson and McIntosh (2002).

  22. Revealingly, in a later work where he reminisces on the development of his views on species distributions, Elton explicitly acknowledges the relevance of Gleason’s “individualistic concept” (Elton and Miller 1954, p. 479; see McIntosh 1995, p. 319).

  23. For discussions of Clements’s ideas on ecological succession, see the references in note 15 above.

  24. For a discussion of the contrast between Clements’s and Tansley’s ideas on succession, see Whittaker (1974) and van der Valk (2014); for further discussion of Elton’s ideas on ecological succession, see Leibold and Wootton (2001, pp. xxv–xxvii).

  25. Historian of ecology Hagen (1992, p. 59) ventures that, living at the time of the 1929 Great Depression and having himself, in that context, lost his job at the Hudson’s Bay Company, Elton could not but be aware that self-regulative processes occurring in human societies were at best imperfect ones compared to those occurring within organisms.

  26. On Elton’s ideas on population regulation and fluctuations, see references in footnote 11.

  27. For a more detailed presentation of Elton’s critique of community selection, see Dussault (forthcoming, sec. 4).

  28. This mode of regulation is commonly referred to by contemporary ecologists as “source-sink dynamics” (see, e.g., Pulliam 1988).

  29. This mode of regulation is commonly called “switching” or “prey switching” by contemporary ecologists (see, e.g., Murdoch 1969).

  30. The contrast between strong and weak regulation I am evoking here is partly inspired by d’Hombres (2012, sec. 4). Unlike d’Hombres, however, I do not restrict strong regulation to regulation involving some kind of centralized control exerted on the parts by the whole. I instead cast the contrast as one between regulation achieved by regulative factors whose behavior has been coordinated by past natural selection, on the one hand, and regulation that arises from the uncoordinated behavior of a system’s freely interacting parts, on the other.

  31. It should also be mentioned that, although I here grant, for the sake of the argument, that Curtis and Whittaker’s studies and Williams’s critique of multilevel selection disqualified the kinds of ecological holism respectively endorsed by Clements and Allee et al., one may question whether this really is the case. For criticisms of Whittaker, see Leibold and Mikkelson (2002) and Wilson et al. (2004); for a partial rehabilitation of community-level selection, see Wilson and Sober (1989).

References

  • Acot, P. (1987). L’idéologie organiciste dans l’histoire récente de l’écologie 1905–1942. Cahiers d’Histoire et de Philosophie des Sciences,22, 73–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agosta, S. J., & Klemens, J. A. (2008). Ecological fitting by phenotypically flexible genotypes: Implications for species associations, community assembly and evolution. Ecology Letters,11(11), 1123–1134. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1461-0248.2008.01237.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allee, W. C., Emerson, A. E., Park, O., Park, T., & Schmidt, K. P. (1949). Principles of animal ecology. Philadelphia: Saunders Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alley, T. R. (1985). Organism-environment mutuality epistemics, and the concept of an ecological niche. Synthese,65(3), 411–444. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00869278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Angner, E. (2009). Hayek and natural law. Milton: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anker, P. (2001). Imperial ecology: Environmental order in the british empire, 1895–1945. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, M. G. (1996). Ecological fragmentation in the fifties. In W. Cronon (Ed.), Uncommon ground: Rethinking the human place in nature (pp. 233–255). New York; London: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergandi, D. (1995). “Reductionist holism”: An oxymoron or a philosophical chimaera of E.P. Odum’s systems ecology? Ludus Vitalis,3(5), 145–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergandi, D. (1999). Les métamorphoses de l’organicisme en écologie: De la communauté végétale aux écosystèmes. Revue d’Histoire des Sciences,52(1), 5–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergandi, D. (2011). Multifaceted ecology between organicism, emergentism and reductionism. In A. Schwarz & K. Jax (Eds.), Ecology revisited: Reflecting on concepts, advancing science (pp. 31–43). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C. (1879). Leçons sur les phénomènes de la vie communs aux animaux et aux végétaux. Paris: Baillière.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bodenheimer, F. S. (1957). The concept of biotic organization in synecology. In F. S. Bodenheimer (Ed.), Studies in biology and its history (pp. 75–90). Jerusalem: Biological Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, J. B. (2003). The implications of the shifting paradigm in ecology for paradigm shifts in the philosophy of conservation. In B. A. Minteer & R. E. Manning (Eds.), Reconstructing conservation: Finding common ground (pp. 239–261). Washington, DC: Island Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canguilhem, G. (2002). Régulation. In Encyclopedia Universalis. https://www.universalis.fr/encyclopedie/regulation-epistemologie/.

  • Canguilhem, G. (2012). The problem of regulation in the organism and in society. In S. Geroulanos & T. Meyers (Eds.), Writings on medicine (pp. 67–78). New York: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cannon, W. B. (1932). The wisdom of the body. New York: W. W. Norton & Company Inc.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carr-Saunders, A. M. (1922). The population problem: A study in human evolution. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Child, C. M. (1924). Physiological foundations of behavior. New York: Henry Holt and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E. (1905). Research methods in ecology. Lincoln, NE: University Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E. (1916). Plant succession: An analysis of the development of vegetation. Washington, DC: Carnegie Institution of Washington.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. E., & Shelford, V. E. (1939). Bioecology. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cox, D. L. (1979). Charles Elton and the emergence of modern ecology (Doctoral dissertation). Saint Louis, MO: Washington University.

  • Crowcroft, P. (1991). Elton’s ecologists: A history of the Bureau of Animal Population. Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press.

  • Curtis, J. T., & McIntosh, R. P. (1951). An upland forest continuum in the prairie-forest border region of Wisconsin. Ecology,32(3), 476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, F. R. (2012). ‘Like a keen north wind’: How charles elton influenced silent spring. Endeavour,36(4), 143–148. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.endeavour.2012.09.004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • d’Hombres, E. (2012). Therapeutic nihilism and administrative nihilism: A non unconditional symmetry. Noesis,20, 151–168.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dussault, A. C. (forthcoming). Functionalism without selectionism: Charles Elton’s “functional” niche and the concept of ecological function. Biological Theory.

  • Egerton, F. N. (1968). Studies of animal populations from Lamarck to Darwin. Journal of the History of Biology,1(2), 225–259. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00351922.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egerton, F. N. (1973). Changing concepts of the balance of nature. The Quarterly Review of Biology,48(2), 322–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egerton, F. N. (2007). Understanding food chains and food webs, 1700–1970. The Bulletin of the Ecological Society of America,88(1), 50–69. https://doi.org/10.1890/0012-9623(2007)88%5b50:UFCAFW%5d2.0.CO;2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliot, C. H. (2007). Method and metaphysics in Clements’s and Gleason’s ecological explanations. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C,38(1), 85–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliot, C. H. (2011). The legend of order and chaos. In K. DeLaplante, B. Brown, & K. A. Peacock (Eds.), Philosophy of ecology (pp. 49–107). Oxford; Amsterdam; Waltham: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S. (1924). Periodic fluctuations in the numbers of animals: Their causes and effects. Journal of Experimental Biology,2(1), 119–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S. (1927). Animal ecology. New York: The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S. (1929). Ecology, animal. In Encyclopædia britannica (14th ed., Vol. 7, pp. 915–924).

  • Elton, C. S. (1930). Animal ecology and evolution. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S. (1932). Fluctuations in wild life. In E. Huntington (Ed.), Matamek conference on biological cycles: Full proceedings, together with a report by Ellsworth Huntington (pp. 11–19). Canadian Labrador: Matamek Factory.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S. (1933). The ecology of animals (3rd ed.). London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S. (1936). Ecology’s survey of the living universe. In J. Hammerton (Ed.), Encyclopedia of modern knowledge (Vol. 2, pp. 1029–1036). London: The Amalgamated Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S. (1950). A fundamental treatise on animal ecology. Journal of Animal Ecology,19(1), 74–78. https://doi.org/10.2307/1572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S. (1958). The ecology of invasions by animals and plants. Chicago: Methuen & Co./Chapman & Hall, Kluwer Academic Publishers B.V.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S. (2001) [1927]. Animal ecology. (M. A. Leibold & J. T. Wootton, Eds.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Elton, C. S., & Miller, R. S. (1954). The ecological survey of animal communities: With a practical system of classifying habitats by structural characters. Journal of Ecology,42(2), 460–496. https://doi.org/10.2307/2256872.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S., & Nicholson, M. R. (1942a). Fluctuations in numbers of the muskrat (Ondatra zibethica) in Canada. Journal of Animal Ecology,11(1), 96–126. https://doi.org/10.2307/1303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elton, C. S., & Nicholson, M. R. (1942b). The ten-year cycle in numbers of the lynx in canada. Journal of Animal Ecology,11(2), 215–244. https://doi.org/10.2307/1358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferrière, A. (1915). La loi du progrès en biologie et en sociologie et la question de l’organisme social. Paris: Giard & Brière.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gay, H. (2013). Silwood circle: A history of ecology and the making of scientific careers in late twentieth-century Britain. London: Imperial College Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, A. H., Kwapich, C. L., & Lang, M. (2013). The roots of multilevel selection: Concepts of biological individuality in the early twentieth century. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences,35(4), 505–532.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glaubrecht, M. (2008). Homage to Karl August Möbius (1825–1908) and his contributions to biology: Zoologist, ecologist, and director at the Museum für Naturkunde in Berlin. Zoosystematics and Evolution,84(1), 9–30. https://doi.org/10.1002/zoos.200700010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gleason, H. A. (1917). The structure and development of the plant association. Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club,44(10), 463–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gleason, H. A. (1926). The individualistic concept of the plant association. Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club,53, 7–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer, J. R. (1990). Modeling in the museum: On the role of remnant models in the work of Joseph Grinnell. Biology and Philosophy,5(1), 3–36. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02423831.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griesemer, J. R. (1992). Niche: Historical perspectives. In E. F. Keller & E. Lloyd (Eds.), Keywords in evolutionary biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grinnell, J. (1917). The niche-relationships of the California Thrasher. Auk,34, 427–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grinnell, J. (1924). Geography and evolution. Ecology,5(3), 225–229. https://doi.org/10.2307/1929447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grinnell, J. (1928). Presence and absence of animals. University of California Chronicle,30, 429–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grinnell, J., & Storer, T. I. (1924). Animal life in the Yosemite: An account of the mammals, birds, reptiles, and amphibians in a cross-section of the Sierra Nevada. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haak, C. (2000). The concept of equilibrium in population ecology (Doctoral dissertation). Halifax, Nova Scotia: Dalhousie University.

  • Hagen, J. B. (1983). The development of experimental methods in plant taxonomy, 1920–1950. Taxon,32(3), 406–416. https://doi.org/10.2307/1221497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagen, J. B. (1988). Organism and environment: Frederic clements’s vision of a unified physiological ecology. In R. Rainger, K. R. Benson, & J. Maienschein (Eds.), The American development of biology (pp. 257–280). Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hagen, J. B. (1992). An entangled bank: The origins of ecosystem ecology. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hébert, Y. (2006). Une histoire de l’écologie au Québec: Les regards sur la nature des origines à nos jours. Québec, QC: Éditions GID.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huntington, E. (1932). Matamek conference on biological cycles: Full proceedings, together with a report by Ellsworth Huntington. Canadian Labrador: Matamek Factory.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, T. H. (1911) [1871]. Administrative nihilism. In Collected essays (Vol. 1 “Method and results”, pp. 251–289). London: D. Appleton and Company.

  • Janzen, D. H. (1985). On ecological fitting. Oikos,45(3), 308–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jax, K. (2010). Ecosystem functioning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kingsland, S. E. (1985). Modeling nature: Episodes in the history of population ecology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibold, M. A. (1995). The niche concept revisited: Mechanistic models and community context. Ecology,76(5), 1371–1382. https://doi.org/10.2307/1938141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leibold, M. A., & Mikkelson, G. M. (2002). Coherence, species turnover, and boundary clumping: Elements of meta-community structure. Oikos,97(2), 237–250. https://doi.org/10.1034/j.1600-0706.2002.970210.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leibold, M. A., & Wootton, J. T. (2001). Introduction. In M. A. Leibold & J. T. Wootton (Eds.), Animal ecology (pp. 19–56). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh, R. P. (1975). H. A. Gleason—“Individualistic ecologist” 1882–1975: His contributions to ecological theory. Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club,102(5), 253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh, R. P. (1980). The relationship between succession and the recovery process in ecosystems. In J. Cairns Jr. (Ed.), The recovery process in damaged ecosystems (pp. 1–62). Ann Arbor, MI: Ann Arbor Science Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh, R. P. (1985). The background of ecology: Concept and theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh, R. P. (1995). H. A. Gleason’s “individualistic concept” and theory of animal communities: A continuing controversy. Biological Reviews of the Cambridge Philosophical Society,70(2), 317–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh, R. P. (1998). The myth of community as organism. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine,14(3), 426–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Möbius, K. (1883). The oyster and oyster culture. Report of the commissioner for fish and fisheries. (H. J. Rice, Trans.) (pp. 683–751). Washington, DC: Government Printing Office.

  • Moore, W. E. (1978). Functionalism. In T. B. Bottomore & R. Nisbet (Eds.), A history of sociological analysis (pp. 321–417). New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, D. W. (2003). Toward an ecological synthesis: A case for habitat selection. Oecologia,136(1), 1–13. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00442-003-1241-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Munch, P. A. (1976). The concept of “function” and functional analysis in sociology. Philosophy of the Social Sciences,6(3), 193–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, W. W. (1969). Switching in general predators: Experiments on predator specificity and stability of prey populations. Ecological Monographs,39(4), 335–354. https://doi.org/10.2307/1942352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neumann, R. P. (2017). Life zones: The rise and decline of a theory of the geographic distribution of species. In R. de Bont & J. Lachmund (Eds.), Spatializing the history of ecology. New York, NY: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315191041-3.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, J. L. (2006). Aldo Leopold’s odyssey. Washington: Island Press/Shearwater Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, A. J. (1933). The balance of animal populations. Journal of Animal Ecology,2, 132–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicolson, M. (1990). Henry A. Gleason and the individualistic hypothesis: The structure of a botanist’s career. Botanical Review,56(1), 91–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicolson, M., & McIntosh, R. P. (2002). H. A. Gleason and the individualistic hypothesis revisited. Bulletin of the Ecological Society of America,83(2), 133–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, F. J., Laland, K. N., & Feldman, M. W. (2003). Niche construction: The neglected process in evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patten, B. C., & Auble, G. T. (1980). Systems approach to the concept of niche. Synthese,43(1), 155–181. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00413861.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pocheville, A. (2015). The ecological niche: History and recent controversies. In T. Heams, P. Huneman, G. Lecointre, & M. Silberstein (Eds.), Handbook of evolutionary thinking in the sciences (pp. 547–586). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pulliam, H. R. (1988). Sources, sinks, and population regulation. The American Naturalist,132(5), 652–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sagoff, M. (1988). Ethics, ecology, and the environment: Integrating science and law. Tennessee Law Review,56, 77–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schoener, T. W. (1989). The ecological niche. In J. M. Cherrett & A. D. Bradshaw (Eds.), Ecological concepts: The contribution of ecology to an understanding of the natural world (pp. 79–114). Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schröter, C., & Kirchner, O. (1902). Die Vegetation des Bodensees. Schriften: Vereins für Geschichte des Bodensees und seiner Umgebung,31, 1–86. (as cited in McIntosh 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, A., & Jax, K. (2011). Early ecology in the German-speaking world through WWII. In A. Schwarz & K. Jax (Eds.), Ecology revisited: Reflecting on concepts, advancing science (pp. 231–275). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sheail, J. (1987). Seventy-five years in ecology: The British ecological society. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelford, V. E. (1907). Preliminary note on the distribution of the tiger beetles (cicindela) and its relation to plant succession. The Biological Bulletin,14(1), 9–14. https://doi.org/10.2307/1535643.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelford, V. E. (1913). Animal communities in temperate America as illustrated in the Chicago region. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelford, V. E. (1931). Some concepts of bioecology. Ecology,12(3), 455–467. https://doi.org/10.2307/1928991.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. (1986). Organismic biology and ecosystems ecology: Description or explanation. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Current issues in teleology (pp. 77–92). Lanham: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. (1980). A succession of paradigms in ecology: Essentialism to materialism and probabilism. Synthese,43(1), 3–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. (2014). The “balance of nature”—Evolution of a panchreston. PLoS Biology,12(10), 1–4. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.1001963.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, H. (1916) [1871]. Specialized administration. In Essays: Scientific, political, and speculative (Vol. 3, pp. 401–444). London: D. Appleton and Company.

  • Summerhayes, V. S., & Elton, C. S. (1923). Contributions to the ecology of Spitsbergen and Bear Island. The Journal of Ecology,11(2), 214–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tansley, A. G. (1920). The classification of vegetation and the concept of development. Journal of Ecology,8(2), 118–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tansley, A. G. (1923). Practical plant ecology. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tansley, A. G. (1935). The use and abuse of vegetational concepts and terms. Ecology,16(3), 284–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tobey, R. C. (1981). Saving the prairie: The life cycle of the founding school of American plant ecology, 1895–1955. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trepl, L., & Voigt, A. (2011). The classical holism–reductionism debate in ecology. In A. Schwarz & K. Jax (Eds.), Ecology revisited: Reflecting on concepts, advancing science (pp. 45–83). Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9744-6_5.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van der Valk, A. (2017). Antecedent wetland ecologists: German and Austrian in the nineteeth century. Wetland Science & Practice,34(4), 112–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Valk, A. G. (2014). From formation to ecosystem: Tansley’s response to clements’ climax. Journal of the History of Biology,47(2), 293–321.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wake, D. B., Hadly, E. A., & Ackerly, D. D. (2009). Biogeography, changing climates, and niche evolution. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,106(Suppl 2), 19631–19636. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0911097106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wells, H. G., Huxley, J., & Wells, C. P. (1931). The science of life. London: Cassell and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker, R. H. (1957). Recent evolution of ecological concepts in relation to the eastern forests of North America. American Journal of Botany,44(2), 197–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker, R. H. (1967). Gradient analysis of vegetation. Biological Reviews,42(2), 207–264. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1469-185X.1967.tb01419.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker, R. H. (1974). Climax concepts and recognition. In R. Knapp (Ed.), Vegetation dynamics (pp. 137–154). Dordrecht: Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2344-3_14.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, C. B. (1964). Patterns in the balance of nature and related problems in quantitative ecology. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. C. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection: A critique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. B., Agnew, A. D. Q., & Sykes, M. (2004). Ecology or mythology? Are Whittaker’s “gradient analysis” curves reliable evidence of continuity in vegetation? Preslia,76(3), 245–253.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. S., & Sober, E. (1989). Reviving the superorganism. Journal of Theoretical Biology,136(3), 337–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worster, D. (1990). The ecology of order and chaos. Environmental History Review,14(1/2), 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yunger, J. (2003). Review of Charles Elton’s animal ecology. Journal of Mammalogy,84(4), 1478–1479. https://doi.org/10.1644/1545-1542(2003)084%3c1478:BR%3e2.0.CO;2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author is thankful to Kurt Jax, Roberta Millstein, and two anonymous referees for helpful comments. He also thanks Xander Selene for editing the manuscript. The work for this paper was supported by a research Grant from the Fonds de recherche du Québec—Société et culture (FRQSC, 2018-CH-211053).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antoine C. Dussault.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dussault, A.C. Neither superorganisms nor mere species aggregates: Charles Elton’s sociological analogies and his moderate holism about ecological communities. HPLS 42, 25 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-020-00316-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-020-00316-z

Keywords

Navigation