Skip to main content
Log in

Fish and fishpond. An ecological reading of G.W. Leibniz’s Monadology §§ 63–70

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One of Leibniz’s most original ideas is his conception of the living individual as a hierarchical network of living beings whose relationships are essential to the proper functioning of its organic body. This idea is also valid to explain any existing order in nature that depends on the set of relationships of living beings that inhabit it. Both ideas are present in the conception of the natural world that Leibniz presents in his Monadology (§§ 63–70) through his idea of biological infinitism. According to this idea, nature consists of infinite theatres (some within others and some unfolding from others) where living beings unfold their vital functions. Through this idea Leibniz defines both the biological complexity of nature and the living individual, which is in turn a portion of nature that unfolds from an infinite set of inferior living beings. The thesis that I defend in this work is that this Leibnizian understanding of the living individual and the natural complexity that includes infinite hierarchical levels of individuality has a marked ecological sense, as we would say today. This Leibnizian metaphysics of individuality that we could call biological is also interesting in light of the recent studies in the philosophy of biology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In addition to the intrinsic difficulty of Leibnizian thought, interpreters are faced with another obstacle: most Leibnizian writings on what we might call 'life sciences' (medicine, anatomy, physiology) have not been transcribed or published yet.

  2. This Leibnizian conception of the individuality as a hierarchical order of individuals has been developed mainly by O. Nachtomy and J.E.H. Smith through their idea of ‘nested individuality’ (Nachtomy et al. 2002; Nachtomy 2007, chapter 9, 2014; Smith 2011, chapter 4). As Nachtomy shows, at this point Leibniz breaks with traditional metaphysics that defends the thesis of ‘a body, a substance’ (Nachtomy 2007, p. 221 and Smith 2011, p. 139).

  3. I would like to understand my paper as a complement to the recent work on the subject published by P. Phemister under the title Leibniz and the environment (Phemister 2016). Phemister's book addresses in much greater depth the implications of an ecological interpretation for Leibnizian thought. I refer any interested reader to this work, whose many achievements I will not be able to mention in this paper for reasons of space.

  4. The first reference corresponds to the edition of the text in the original, the second to the translation used. For the abbreviations of the original editions see the list of references at the end of the paper.

  5. I cannot stress enough the relevance of analysing in depth these three problems. However, it is important to say that Leibniz's departure from these three problems from the idea of biological infinitism is something that we only find in his mature monadological philosophy, which made this idea gain a key position in Leibniz's metaphysic as compared to its earliest formulations. For a more extensive development of these problems, I recommend reading the exhaustive work of P. Phemister Leibniz and the natural world (2005). On the problem of the continuum, see also: Arthur (1998) and Orio de Miguel (2011).

  6. One of the most original parts of Phemister’s ecological interpretation of Leibniz (Phemister 2016) is precisely the analysis of this psychic dimension (perceptive–appetitive) of Leibniz's theory of space (chapters 6 and 7).

  7. The idea of machine or mechanism is present in most of Leibniz's contemporaries. As Andrault (2016) shows in her study on this subject, the meaning that each one of them gives to this idea is different.

  8. Although on an epistemological level Leibniz recognizes the heuristic value of mechanisms in describing the bodies of living beings, these descriptions are still fictions of our understanding, which do not (cannot) account for the reality of the living world. For Leibniz, the definitions we have of natural species are 'provisional and proportional to our knowledge'. We know little, he says, both about the internal constitution of biological species and about their natural generation (see New Essays, book III, chapter VI). At an ontological level an ecological interpretation of Leibnizian conception of the natural world and living organisms is more appropriate than a mechanistic reading.

  9. This problem is pointed out by Dumas (1976, p. 125). See also Andrault (2017).

  10. They could be others, for example, in human societies.

  11. The idea of entity, being or unit by aggregation is discussed at length in Leibniz's correspondence with A. Arnauld and B. Des Bosses. The idea of ‘substantiated being’ not only appears in the correspondence with B. Des Bosses (GP II, pp. 403, 439, 459), which must be cited with caution due to its peculiarity (see Look 1999), but is also present in other texts (Couturat, p. 13, GP VI, p. 625 or LH, I, I, 4, fol.48, manuscript translated and published in Velarde Lombraña 2001, pp. 137–138). The question of the reality of aggregates (bodies or communities of living beings) is problematic and would merit further analysis. Leibniz is ambiguous and even sometimes contradictory on this issue.

References

  • Andrault, R. (2016). La raison des corps. Mécanisme et sciences médicales (1664–1720). Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andrault, R. (2017). Leibniz et la connaissance du vivant. In L. Mogens, L. Christian, & R. David (Eds.), Leibniz. Lectures et commentaires (pp. 171–190). Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, R., & Garber, D. (1989). G.W. Leibniz: Philosophical Essays. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, R. T. W. (1998). Infinite aggregates and phenomenal wholes: Leibniz’s theory of substance as a solution to the continuum problem. Leibniz Society Review,8, 25–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becchi, A. (2016). Leibniz’ Harlequin and the theater of organic bodies. In L. Wenchao (Ed.), Für unser Glück oder das Glück anderer. Vorträge des X. Internationalen Leibniz-Kongresses (Vol. 2, pp. 401–416). Hildesheim: Georg Olms Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becchi, A. (2017). Leibniz, the microscope and the conceptof preformation. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences. https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-017-0130-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duchesneau, F., & Smith, J. E. H. (2016). The Leibniz-Stahl controversy. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dumas, M.-N. (1976). Le pensée de la vie chez Leibniz. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S. F., Sapp, J., & Tauber, A. I. (2012). A symbiotic view of life: We have never been individuals. The Quarterly Review of Biology,87(4), 325–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, S. F., & Tauber, A. I. (2016). Rethinking individuality: The dialectics of the holobiont. Biology and Philosophy,31, 839–853.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2014a). Individuality as a theoretical scheme. I. Formal and material concepts of individuality. Biological Theory,9, 361–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2014b). Individuality as a theoretical scheme. II. About the weak individuality of organism and ecosystems. Biological Theory,9, 374–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2014c). Kant versus Leibniz in the second antinomy: Organisms are not infinitely subtle machines. Kant-Studien. https://doi.org/10.1515/kant-2014-0009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langley, A. G. (1896). New essays concerning human understanding by G.W. Leibnitz. New York: The MacMillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latta, R. (1898). Leibniz: The Monadology and other philosophical writings. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G.W. (1903). [Couturat]. Opuscules et Fragments Inédits de Leibniz. L. Couturat. (Ed.) Paris: Félix Alcan (reprint, Hildesheim: Olms, 1966).

  • Leibniz, G.W. (1923). [A]. Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe. Ed. Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften. Darmstadt/Leipzig/Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

  • Leibniz, G.W. (1954). [Robinet]. G.W. Leibniz. Principes de la nature et de la grâce fondés en raison. Principes de la philosophie ou Monadologie, publiés intégralement d’après les manuscrits d’Hanovre, Vienne et Paris et présentés d’après des lettres inédites par A. Robinet. A. Robinet, (Ed.) París: PUF.

  • Leibniz, G.W. (1978). [GP]. Die philosophische Schriften von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. C.I. Gerhardt (Ed.) Hildesheim: Georg Olms.

  • Leibniz, G.W. (1985). Theodicy, A. Farrer and translated by E.M. Huggard, (Ed.) La Salle, Illinois: Open Court (online edition).

  • Leibniz, G.W. (1989). [Dutens]. G.G. Leibnitii Opera Omnia. L. Dutens (Ed.) Hildesheim: Olms.

  • Leibniz, G.W. (1993). Protogaea: de l’aspect primitif de la terre. Ed. and trans. J.-M. Barrande. Toulouse: Presses Universitaires du Mirail.

  • Leibniz, G.W. (1997). [Finster]. G.W. Leibniz. Der Briefwechsel mit Antoine Arnauld. R. Finster (Ed.) Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.

  • Look, B. (1999). Leibniz and the ‘Vinculum Substantiale’. Studia Leibnitiana Sonderheft 30. Stuttgart: Steiner Verlag.

  • Nachtomy, O. (2007). Possibility, agency and individuality in Leibniz’s metaphysics. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nachtomy, O. (2014). The role of infinity in Leibniz´s theory of livings beings. In O. Nachtomy & J. E. H. Smith (Eds.), The life science in early modern philosophy (pp. 9–29). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nachtomy, O., Shavit, A., & Smith, J. E. H. (2002). Leibnizian organism, nested individuals, and units of selections. Theory in Biosciences,12(2), 205–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orio de Miguel, B. (2011). Leibniz: Crítica de la razón simbólica. Comares: Granada.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phemister, P. (2005). Leibniz and the natural world. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Phemister, P. (2016). Leibniz and the environment. London and New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pradeu, T. (2010). What is an organism? An immunological answer. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences,32, 247–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradeu, T. (2016). Organism or biological individuals? Combining physiological and evolutionary individuality. Biology and Philosophy,31(6), 797–817.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. E. H. (2011). Divine machines: Leibniz and the sciences of life. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Velarde Lombraña, J. (2001). Leibniz. Monadología. Principios de filosofía. Madrid: Biblioteca Nueva.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, C. (1995). The invisible world: Early modern philosophy and the invention of the microscope. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

A previous version of this article was presented at the Workshop related to the project ‘The origins of modern science in Europe: G.W. Leibniz’ (Acción Integrada Hispano-Portuguesa, Lisboa 14-15 september 2018). I am grateful to all participants for their comments. This paper has also benefited from the suggestions and comments of Sabina Leonelli (editor in chief of HPLS) and two anonymous reviewers. I would especially like to thank Bernardino Orio de Miguel for his comments.

Funding

Funding was provided by Ministerio de Ciencia, Innovación y Universidades (Grant No. FJCI-2017-33649 and PGC2018-094692-B-I00) and Basque Goverment (ES) (Grant No. IT1228-19).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miguel Escribano-Cabeza.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Escribano-Cabeza, M. Fish and fishpond. An ecological reading of G.W. Leibniz’s Monadology §§ 63–70. HPLS 42, 23 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-020-00319-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-020-00319-w

Keywords

Navigation