Skip to main content
Log in

Path Integrals and Holism

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper argues that the path integral formulation of quantum mechanics suggests a form of holism for which the whole (total ensemble of paths) has properties that are not strongly reducible to the properties of the parts (the single trajectories). Feynman’s sum over histories calculates the probability amplitude of a particle moving within a boundary by summing over all the possible trajectories that the particle can undertake. These trajectories and their individual probability amplitudes are thus necessary in calculating the total amplitude. However, not all possible trajectories are differentiable, thus suggesting that they are not physical possibilities, but only mathematical entities. It follows that if the possible differentiable trajectories are taken to be part of the physical system, they are not sufficient to calculate the total probability amplitude. The conclusion is that the total ensemble is weakly non-supervenient upon the physically possible trajectories.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a more comprehensive mathematical treatment see, among others: [3, 16, 45].

  2. To be more precise, in the classical limit \(\hbar \rightarrow 0\), the main constructive interfering paths are those in the infinitesimal neighborhood (in the order of the quantum of action) of the stationary paths.

  3. It can be shown by proving that it is the path that minimizes the action.

  4. For the present purposes, it is sufficient to take supervenience as a form of reductionism where the properties of set \(\alpha\) can be determined (reduced) by the properties of set \(\beta\).

  5. To be precise, [27] also distinguishes properties that are qualitative, i.e., properties that to be instantiated do not depend on the existence of a particular object or individual.

  6. We have been cutting around some corners and we have not covered the large and prolific debate about both atomism, supervenience and their relation with classical mechanics. See, among others: [23, 27, 32, 35, 37].

  7. The point was also raised in [22].

  8. The specification of the supervenience basis is necessary so as not to make supervenience trivial.

  9. To be precise, the system follows the path for which the action is stationary

  10. For the mathematical details see: (Wharton [49], p. 5).

  11. One can conceive of this last case as the difficulty of calculating the exact outcome of a dice-tossing because of the presence of variables such as the friction between the dice and the surface, the exact strength of the tossing, the imperfections of the shape of the dice and so on.

  12. The mathematical details do not concern us here, but can be found in: [7] and [10].

  13. For the details of the proof, see: Feynman et al. ([7], p. 176)

  14. For a better and more detailed exposition of such interpretation see: [12, 17, 18].

  15. Such an idea of probability fits more the objective probability expressed by the quote from Feynman we have introduced in the previous subsection. As such, it is also different from the epistemic probability advocated by Wharton.

  16. A realm is a set of decoherent coarse-grained alternative histories.

  17. I am leaving aside the mathematical details as not relevant for our purposes here.

  18. One might promptly note that if a reduction of the ensemble is possible, then the total amplitude does not depend on each single trajectory. One could consider this as a further weakening of the non-supervenience or, alternatively, simply take the ensemble to be the smallest set of trajectories necessary to obtain the appropriate total probability amplitude.

  19. We are assuming the condition that there are no obstacles within the boundary that could determine a bouncing of the particle.

  20. For a trajectory to be (non) physical corresponds to the concrete possibility for a particle to traverse it.

  21. A third possibility would be to discuss whether trajectories can be non-local. The argument would require a longer investigation on the non-local nature of quantum mechanics. Nonetheless, it is opinion of the author that this would lead to a case of holism by analogy with entanglement. We leave the issue to further investigations.

References

  1. Barut, A.O., Basri, S.: Path integrals and quantum interference. Am. J. Phys. 60(10), 896–899 (1992)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  2. Belousek, D.W.: Non-seperability, non-supervenience, and quantum ontology. Philos. Sci. 70(4), 791–811 (2003)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  3. Chaichian, M., Demichev, A.: Path integrals in physics. Vol. 1 Stochastic processes and quantum mechanics. CRC Press, Boca Raton (2001)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. Cleland, C.E.: Space: an abstract system of non-supervenient relations. Philos. Stud. 46(1), 19–40 (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Englert, B.-G.: Fringe visibility and which-way information: an inequality. Phys. Rev. Lett. 77(11), 2154 (1996)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  6. Esfeld, M.: Quantum entanglement and a metaphysics of relations. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. B 35(4), 601–617 (2004)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Feynman, R.P., Hibbs, A.R., Styer, D.F.: Quantum Mechanics and Path Integrals. Courier Corporation, North Chlemsford (2010)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Feynman, R.P. et al.: The concept of probability in quantum mechanics. In: Proceedings of the Second Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics and Probability, Vol. 533. Berkeley, CA (1951)

  9. Feynman, R.P., Leighton, R.B., Sands, M.: The Feynman Lectures on Physics. Vol. 2: Mainly Electromagnetism and Matter. Addison-Wesley, New York (1979)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Feynman, R.P.: Space–time approach to non-relativistic quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 20(2), 367–387 (1948)

    ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. French, S.: Individuality, supervenience and Bell’s theorem. Philos. Stud. 55(1), 1–22 (1989)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  12. Gell-Mann, M., Hartle, J.B.: Quantum mechanics in the light of quantum cosmology. Complexity, Entropy and the Physics of Information. Addison-Wesley, Boston (1990)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Gell-Mann, M., Hartle, J.B.: Decoherent histories quantum mechanics with one real fine-grained history. Phys. Rev. A 85(6), 062120 (2012)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  14. Greenberger, D.M., Yasin, A.: Simultaneous wave and particle knowledge in a neutron interferometer. Phys. Lett. A 128(8), 391–394 (1988)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  15. Griffiths, R.B.: Consistent histories and the interpretation of quantum mechanics. J. Stat. Phys. 36(1–2), 219–272 (1984)

    ADS  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Grosche, C., Steiner, F.: Handbook of Feynman Path Integrals. Springer, Berlin (1998)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  17. Halliwell, J.J.: A review of the decoherent histories approach to quantum mechanics. Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci. 755(1), 726–740 (1995)

    ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  18. Hartle, J.B.: Spacetime quantum mechanics and the quantum mechanics of spacetime. In: arXiv preprint arXiv:gr-qc/9304006 (1993)

  19. Hartle, J.B.: What connects different interpretations of quantum mechanics? Quo Vadis Quantum Mechanics?, pp. 73–82. Springer, Berlin (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Hartle, J.B.: The spacetime approach to quantum mechanics. Vistas Astron. 37, 569–583 (1993)

    ADS  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  21. Healey, R.: Holism and Nonseparability in Physics (1999)

  22. Healey, R.A.: Holism and nonseparability. J. Philos. 88(8), 393–421 (1991)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  23. Howard, D.: Einstein on locality and separability. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. A 16(3), 171–201 (1985)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  24. Howard, D.: Holism, separability, and the metaphysical implications of the Bell experiments. In: Philosophical consequences of quantum theory: resections on Bell’s theorem, pp. 224–253 (1989)

  25. Jaeger, G., Shimony, A., Vaidman, L.: Two interferometric complementarities. Phys. Rev. A 51(1), 54 (1995)

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  26. Joas, C., Lehner, C.: The classical roots of wave mechanics: Schrödinger’s transformations of the optical-mechanical analogy. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. B 40(4), 338–351 (2009)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Karakostas, V.: Atomism versus holism in science and philosophy: the case of humean supervenience. In: Science Education in Focus, p. 253 (2008)

  28. Kent, A.: Path integrals and reality. In: arXiv preprint (2013) arXiv:1305.6565

  29. Ladyman, J.: What is structural realism? Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. A 29(3), 409–424 (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  30. Lancaster, T., Blundell, S.J.: Quantum Field Theory for the Gifted Amateur. OUP, Oxford (2014)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  31. Lange, M.: Because Without Cause: Non-causal Explanations in Science and Mathematics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2016)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  32. Lewis, D.: Philosophical Papers, vol. II. Springer, New York (1986)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  33. Machamer, P., Darden, L., Craver, C.F.: Thinking about mechanisms. Philos. Sci. 67(1), 1–25 (2000)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  34. MacKenzie, R.: Path integral methods and applications. In: arXiv preprint arXiv:quant-ph/0004090 (2000)

  35. McLaughlin, B., Bennett, K.: Supervenience. In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Stanford (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  36. McLaughlin, B., Bennett, K.: Supervenience. In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Stanford (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  37. Myrvold, W.C.: Nonseparability, classical, and quantum. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 62(2), 417–432 (2010)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  38. Seevinck, M.P.: Holism, physical theories and quantum mechanics. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. B 35(4), 693–712 (2004)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  39. Sharlow, M.: The quantum mechanical path integral: toward a realistic interpretation (2007)

  40. Smart, B.T.H., Thébault, K.P.Y.: Dispositions and the principle of least action revisited. Analysis 75(3), 386–395 (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Stöltzner, M.: The principle of least action as the logical empiricist’s Shibboleth. Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. B 34(2), 285–318 (2003)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  42. Straub, W.O.: Simplified Path Integral Approach to the Aharonov–Bohm Effect. In: Pasadena, California 91104 (2014)

  43. Teller, P.: Relational holism and quantum mechanics. Br. J. Philos. Sci. 36, 71–81 (1986)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  44. Terekhovich, V.: Ontological foundations of the variational principles and the path integral formalism. In: arXiv preprint arXiv:1909.10064 (2019)

  45. Townsend, J.S.: A Modern Approach to Quantum Mechanics. University Science Books, Mill Valley (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  46. Tumulka, R.: Feynman’s path integrals and Bohm’s particle paths. Eur. J. Phys. 26(3), L11 (2005)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  47. Wharton, K.: Quantum states as ordinary information. Information 5(1), 190–208 (2014)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  48. Wharton, K.: The universe is not a computer. Questioning the Foundations of Physics, pp. 177–189. Springer, Berlin (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  49. Wharton, K.: Towards a realistic parsing of the Feynman Path Integral. In: Quanta 5.1 (2016)

  50. Worrall, J.: Structural realism: the best of both worlds? Dialectica 43(1–2), 99–124 (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  51. Yagisawa, T.: Possible objects. In: Zalta, E. (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2018). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, Stanford (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  52. Zee, A.: Quantum Field Theory in a Nutshell. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2010)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Forgione.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Forgione, M. Path Integrals and Holism. Found Phys 50, 799–827 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-020-00351-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-020-00351-7

Keywords

Navigation