Skip to main content
Log in

Re-forming Morphology: Two Attempts to Rehabilitate the Problem of Form in the First Half of the Twentieth Century

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Journal of the History of Biology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. In case it is not apparent, the claims of this paragraph are intended to convey the view of those who discerned in the early twentieth century the seeds of a revolution in the sciences. They are not my own views.

  2. To be precise, Needham called morphology itself “the last stronghold of irrationalist views” in the natural sciences. The occasion was a memorial publication for D’Arcy Thompson: “[It] was precisely because D’Arcy Thompson considered morphology the last stronghold of irrationalist views that he devoted his life to the mathematization of it” (1951, p. 79).

  3. Older studies include Haraway (1976), Roll-Hansen (1984), Harrington (1996) and Allen (2004, 2005).

  4. An exception is embryology, which has received detailed treatments, for example, from Haraway (1976), Allen (2004), and Peterson (2011, 2014, 2017).

  5. Keller slightly overstates the point. The sixteenth chapter of Growth and Form leans heavily on the notion of mechanical fitness (i.e., the biomechanical efficiency of a structure for a task); hence, at least in this instance, some notion of function seems to be operative. See also Dresow (2017).

  6. More distantly related forms are a separate matter. These forms cannot be easily converted into one another by means of a geometrical transformation; in Gould’s words, they have to be treated as “‘primitive terms’ … as ‘givens’ to be acknowledged (and attributed to other kinds of causes)” (2002, p. 1199). Here history reenters morphology in an obtrusive way.

  7. Pouvreau and Drack’s outstanding article (2007) represents a watershed in our understanding of Bertalanffy’s biology. Perhaps their most important contribution was to highlight the depth of Bertalanffy’s debt to the neo-Kantian tradition, which had been neglected in earlier scholarship. This section is much indebted to their penetrating analysis.

  8. Pouvreau and Drack (2007) trace the history of these organismic principles through their various formulations.

  9. Equifinality is the ability of a system to achieve the same goal or end-state despite variation in initial conditions and/or pathways of attainment. Examples of equifinal behavior include the development of a “normal” adult organism from an intact, divided, or fused ovum, and the attainment of a definite size from different starting sizes, using different pathways of growth.

  10. For issues with Bertalanffy’s derivation, see Pouvreau and Drack (2007, pp. 319, 328–330).

  11. It is here, perhaps, that Bertalanffy’s debt to Thompson is most pronounced. Bertalanffy was an admirer of Thompson and seems to have taken from him a general sense that biology needs to be mathematized. But he also took over a very specific framing of the problem of form: that it amounts to a problem of relative growth. This was appealing since relative growth was tractable using currently available mathematical tools (like differential equations).

  12. Here is Thompson: “Except in certain minute organisms, whose form (like that of a drop of water) is due to the direct action of the molecular forces, we may look upon the form of an organism as a ‘function of growth,’ or a direct consequence of growth whose rate varies in its different directions” (Thompson 1917, p. 154).

  13. This assessment is complicated somewhat by the many meanings of the term mechanism: a topic that both Thompson and Bertalanffy discussed (e.g., Thompson 1918; Bertalanffy 1932). Still, there can be little doubt that the two men diverged in their general attitudes, to say nothing of their visceral reactions, towards the broad cluster of mechanistic ideas.

References

  • Allen, Garland. 1975. Life Science in the Twentieth Century. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen, Garland. 2004. A Pact with the Embryo: Viktor Hamburger, Holistic and Mechanistic Philosophy in the Development of Neuroembryology, 1927–1955. Journal of the History of Biology 37: 421–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, Garland. 2005. Mechanism, Vitalism and Organicism in Late Nineteenth and Twentieth-Century Biology: The Importance of Historical Context. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36: 261–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baedke, Jan. 2019. O Organism, Where Art Thou? Old and New Challenges for Organism-Centered Biology. Journal of the History of Biology 52: 293–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1928. Kritische Theorie der Formbildung. Berlin: Gebrüder Borntraeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1932. Theoretische Biologie—I. Band. Berlin: Gebrüder Borntraeger.

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1933. Modern Theories of Development: An Introduction to Theoretical Biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1937. Das Gefüge des Lebens. Leipzig: Teubner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1942. Theoretische Biologie—Band II. Berlin: Gebrüder Borntraeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1949. Problems of Organic Growth. Nature 164: 156–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1950a. An Outline of General System Theory. British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 1: 134–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1950b. The Theory of Open Systems in Physics and Biology. Science 111: 23–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1951a. Theoretical Models in Biology and Psychology. Journal of Personality 20: 24–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1951b. Goethe’s Concept of Nature. Main Currents in Modern Thought 8: 78–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1952. Problems of Life: An Evaluation of Modern Biological Thought. London: Watts and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1955. An Essay on the Relativity of the Categories. Philosophy of Science 22: 243–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackman, Helen J. 2007. The Natural Sciences and the Development of Animal Morphology in Late-Victorian Cambridge. Journal of the History of Biology 40: 71–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, Peter. 1996. Life’s Splendid Drama: Evolutionary Biology and the Reconstruction of Life’s Ancestry, 1860–1940. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, Peter. 2001. Reconciling Science and Religion: The Debate in Early Twentieth-Century Britain. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bruce, Robin W. 2014. A Reflection on Biological Thought: Whatever Happened to the Organism? Biological Journal of the Linnean Society 112: 354–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drack, Manfred. 2009. Ludwig Bertalanffy’s Early System Approach. Systems Research and Behavioral Science 26: 563–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dresow, Max. 2017. Before Hierarchy: The Rise and Fall of Stephen Jay Gould’s First Macroevolutionary Synthesis. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 39: 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esposito, Maurizio. 2013. Romantic Biology, 1890–1945. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposito, Maurizio. 2014. Problematic Idiosyncrasies: Rediscovering the Historical Context of D’Arcy Wentworth Thompson’s Science of Form. Science in Context 27: 79–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, Stephen Jay. 2002. The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, Donna. 1976. Crystals, Fabrics and Fields: Metaphors that Shape Embryos. Berkeley, CA: North Atlantic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrington, Anne. 1996. Reenchanted Science: Holism in German Culture from Wilhelm II to Hitler. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hogben, Lancelot. 1930. The Nature of Living Matter. London: Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, Evelyn Fox. 2002. Making Sense of Life: Explaining Biological Development with Models, Metaphors, and Machines. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loeb, Jacques. 1912. The Mechanistic Conception of Life. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lovejoy, Arthur. 1911. The Meaning of Vitalism. Science 33: 610–614.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Needham, Joseph. 1928. Recent Developments in the Philosophy of Biology. The Quarterly Review of Biology 3: 77–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Needham, Joseph. 1951. Biochemical Aspects of Form and Growth. In Aspects of Form: A Symposium on Form in Nature and Art, ed. L.L. Whyte, 77–90. London: Percy Lund Humphries.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, Daniel, and Richard Gawne. 2015. Neither Logical Empiricism nor Vitalism: What Philosophy of Biology Was. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 37: 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nyhart, Lynn. 1987. The Disciplinary Breakdown of German Morphology: 1870–1900. Isis 78: 365–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, Erik. 2011. The Excluded Philosophy of Evo-Devo? Revisiting C.H. Waddington’s Failed Attempt to Embed Alfred North Whitehead’s “Organicism” in Evolutionary Biology. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 33: 301–320.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, Erik. 2014. The Conquest of Vitalism or the Eclipse of Organicism? The 1930s Cambridge Organizer Project and the Social Network of Mid-Twentieth-Century Biology. The British Journal for the History of Science 47: 281–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, Erik. 2017. The Life Organic: The Theoretical Biology Club and the Roots of Epigenetics. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pouvreau, David, and Manfred Drack. 2007. On the History of Ludwig von Bertalanffy’s ‘General Systemology’, and on its Relationship to Cybernetics—Part I: Elements on the Origins and Genesis of Ludwig von Bertalanffy’s “General Systemology”. International Journal of General Systems 36: 281–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roll-Hansen, Nils. 1984. E. S. Russell and J. H. Woodger: The Failure of Two Twentieth-Century Opponents of Mechanistic Biology. Journal of the History of Biology 17: 399–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smuts, Jan Christian. 1931. The Scientific World-Picture of To-Day. Science 74: 297–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, D’Arcy Wentworth. 1913. On Aristotle as a Biologist, with a Prooemion on Herbert Spencer. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, D’Arcy Wentworth. 1917. On Growth and Form. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, D’Arcy Wentworth. 1918. Symposium: Are Physical Biological and Psychological Categories ReducibleII. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society; N.S. vol. 18 (1917–1918). London: Williams and Norgate, pp. 436–471.

  • Whitehead, Alfred North. 1925. Science and the Modern World. New York: Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Edmund Beecher. 1908. Biology. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodger, Joseph Henry. 1929. Biological Principles: A Critical Study. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to extend my gratitude to Marco Tamborini for inviting me to contribute to this special issue, and for his generous support and encouragement. I would also like to thank the participants in “On Growth and Form: A Centennial Perspective”—a workshop celebrating the 100th anniversary of On Growth and Form, held at Saint Andrews College. Two anonymous referees greatly enhanced the quality of this paper. Finally, thank you to my ‘lab mates’ at the University of Minnesota for helpful comments on an early draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Max Dresow.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dresow, M. Re-forming Morphology: Two Attempts to Rehabilitate the Problem of Form in the First Half of the Twentieth Century. J Hist Biol 53, 231–248 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10739-020-09603-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10739-020-09603-8

Navigation