Skip to main content
Log in

Pictures, Plants, and Propositions

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Philosophers have traditionally held that propositions mark the domain of rational thought and inference. Many philosophers have held that only conceptually sophisticated creatures like us could have propositional attitudes. But in recent decades, philosophers have adopted increasingly liberal views of propositional attitudes that encompass the mental states of various non-human animals. These views now sit alongside more traditional views within the philosophical mainstream. In this paper I argue that liberalized views of propositional attitudes are so liberal that they encompass states of all sorts of apparently mindless systems like circadian clocks in plants. I begin by arguing that on the most well-developed and widely endorsed theories of underived representation in philosophy, circadian clocks qualify as representations. I then argue that standard reasons for thinking that perceptual states and pictures have propositional content carry over to circadian clocks. Finally, I argue that circadian representations in plants play the kind of functional role that is widely taken to be partly constitutive of belief-like attitudes. So according to mainstream theories of representation, propositions, and attitudes, plants have propositional attitudes. Yet on other more traditional views, this conclusion would seem absurd. So, contrary to appearances, there is no shared, stable understanding of what propositional attitudes are in contemporary philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As I hope will become clear later, I am not here intending to cast a skeptical light on the extensional adequacy of these scientific distinctions (here, at least). The question I am interested in is whether the notion of a propositional attitude is empirically grounded enough to capture these distinctions.

  2. I recognize that several philosophers and biologists have recently drawn from the scientific literature on ‘plant intelligence’ to argue that plants indeed have minds (Maher 2017; Gagliano 2017; Calvo 2017). I don’t dispute this claim here. I largely prescind from empirical theses in this paper to explore the commitments about different views of propositional representation.

  3. Not all interpretivist views are liberal. According to Davidson’s (1973, 1982) version of interpretivism, only language-using systems have propositional attitudes.

  4. See Ben-Yami (1997) for a sense of just how thin the historical reasons for thinking that mental states are propositional attitudes really were.

  5. I am here just reporting a dominant line of thought, not endorsing it. For some critical discussion of this way of conceptualizing and naturalizing intentionality, see Morgan and Piccinini (2017).

  6. I cannot do justice to the important differences between the views that I am classifying as tracking theories within the scope of this paper. That it is reasonable to treat these theories as variations on the same basic theme is now widely assumed in the literature (Burge 2010; Kriegel 2012; Mendelovici, 2013). I say more by way justifying this assumption in Morgan (forthcoming), where I also argue that Burge’s (2010) influential view, which is trenchantly opposed to tracking theories, is simply another variant of this same basic theme.

  7. From the Latin ‘circa’ (approximately) and ‘diēm’ (day).

  8. For more details about the properties described in this paragraph and references to the experimental literature, see Gardner et al. (2006) and McClung (2006).

  9. I put ‘day’ in quotes because I am writing not of actual daytime, but of represented daytime. In the biological literature, this distinction is standardly marked by writing of ‘subjective’ day or night. This underscores the general point that it is difficult if not impossible to explain clock-mediated behavior without positing representational content.

  10. It is not clear that clocks are literally ‘selected’ to play control functions here, but it is not clear that neurons are literally ‘selected’ in the process of animal learning either (Crick 1989; Quartz and Sejnowski 1997). The notion of selection is at best an illustrative metaphor for Dretske. What is theoretically important for him is simply the idea that content plays a role in explaining the behavior of individual organisms.

  11. Though not universally. See, for example, Brewer (2006) and Travis (2004).

  12. Note that when I write of ‘pictures’ and ‘pictorial content’ here, I specifically have in mind the representational features of pictures. Not all pictures are representational in the sense that they purport to depict some specific state of affairs, and even those that are might be said to have a kind of non-representational expressive or affective content. Like Crane, I focus only on the representational features of pictures.

  13. Crane has an independent line of argument against the propositional view of pictorial content, based on the idea that pictures do not stand in the logical relations that propositions necessarily do. Grzankowski (2015) ably shows that this rests on another vehicle-content confusion, so I needn’t engage with this argument here.

  14. One might also hold that plant clocks play a desire-like, telic role since they serve to guide the plant’s activities. In that case they would qualify as what Millikan (1995) calls ‘pushmi-pullyu’ representations. I am not primarily concerned in this paper to identify precisely what kind of attitudinal role plant circadian clocks play; my main goal is just to show that they play some such role or other. I should note that nothing I say here provides reason to think plants can have several different kinds of attitude. Interpretivists would reject ‘punctate’ propositional attitudes on grounds that attitude ascription is necessarily holistic (Davidson 1973), but I think most of the realists I am engaging with here would admit the possibility of punctate attitudes. Still, some might deny this. As I’ll go on to discuss shortly, realists might invoke various reasons for resisting the conclusion that plants have genuine attitudes—but in doing so they’re bound to make assumptions that other realists would find deeply implausible.

  15. Chisholm appealed to a third criterion, but this is not relevant for my purposes so I leave it out for the sake of expository clarity.

  16. I remain officially neutral on the question of whether this implies that capacities like inference are ubiquitous in nature, or that standard views of such capacities are empirically inadequate. I happen to believe the latter, but this biographical fact is irrelevant to the conditional thesis of this paper.

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (1994). Fodorian semantics. In S. Stich & T. Warfield (Eds.), Mental representation: A reader (pp. 223–242). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J. (1980). Concepts, propositions, and schemata: What are the cognitive units? In J. Flowers (Ed.), Nebraska symposium on motivation: Cognitive processes (pp. 121–162). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Yami, H. (1997). Against characterizing mental states as propositional attitudes. Philosophical Quarterly, 47(186), 84–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (2006). Perception and content. European Journal of Philosophy, 14(2), 165–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bünning, E. (1973). The Physiological Clock. New York, NY: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2004). Perception and conceptual content. In E. Sosa & M. Steup (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 231–250). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvo, P. (2017). What is it like to be a plant? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 24(9–10), 205–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2004). On being simple minded. American Philosophical Quarterly, 41(3), 205–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavallari, N., et al. (2011). A blind circadian clock in cavefish reveals that opsins mediate peripheral clock photoreception. PLoS Biology, 9(9), e1001142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1955). Sentences about believing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 125–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M., & Newsome, W. (2004). What electrical microstimulation has revealed about the neural basis of cognition. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 14(2), 169–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craik, K. (1943). The nature of explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2009). Is perception a propositional attitude? The Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236), 452–469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. (1989). Neural Edelmanism. Trends in Neurosciences, 12(7), 240–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons, and causes. The Journal of Philosophy, 60(23), 685–700.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1973). Radical interpretation. Dialectica, 27(3–4), 313–328.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1982). Rational animals. Dialectica, 36(4), 317–327.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Real patterns. The Journal of Philosophy, 88(1), 27–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickinson, A. (1980). Contemporary animal learning theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987a). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987b). Why paramecia don’t have mental representations. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10(1), 3–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gagliano, M. (2017). The mind of plants: Thinking the unthinkable. Communicative & Integrative Biology, 10(2), e1288333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gagliano, M., et al. (2016). Learning by association in plants. Scientific Reports, 6, 38427.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. (1998). Symbolic processes in the brain: The case of insect navigation. In D. Scarborough & D. Sternberg (Eds.), An invitation to cognitive science: Methods, models, and conceptual issues (pp. 1–52). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. (2008). Learning and representation. In J. Byrne (Ed.), Learning and memory: A comprehensive reference (Vol. 1, pp. 227–242). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, M., Hubbard, K., Hotta, C., Dodd, A., & Webb, A. (2006). How plants tell the time. Biochemical Journal, 397(1), 15–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodspeed, D., Chehab, E., Min-Venditti, A., Braam, J., & Covington, M. (2012). Arabidopsis synchronizes jasmonate-mediated defense with insect circadian behavior. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 109(12), 4674–4677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grzankowski, A. (2015). Pictures have propositional content. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 6(1), 151–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, P., et al. (1990). Feedback of the drosophila period gene product on circadian cycling of its messenger RNA levels. Nature, 343(6258), 536–540.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasegawa, Y., & Arita, M. (2014). Circadian clocks optimally adapt to sunlight for reliable synchronization. Journal of the Royal Society, Interface, 11(92), 20131018.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heck, R. (2000). Nonconceptual content and the ‘space of reasons’. Philosophical Review, 109(4), 483–523.

    Google Scholar 

  • Isaac, A. (2013). Objective similarity and mental representation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(4), 683–704.

    Google Scholar 

  • Konopka, R., & Benzer, S. (1971). Clock mutants of drosophila melanogaster. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 68(9), 2112–2116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2012). Personal-level representation. Protosociology, 28, 77–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, C. (2017). Plant minds: A philosophical defense. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, J. (1979). Ascribing mental qualities to machines. In M. Ringle (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives in artificial intelligence. Newark, NJ: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClung, C. (2006). Plant circadian rhythms. The Plant Cell, 18(4), 792–803.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mendelovici, A. (2013). Reliable misrepresentation and tracking theories of mental representation. Philosophical Studies, 165(2), 421–443.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1995). Pushmi-pullyu representations. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 185–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, C., De Houwer, J., & Lovibond, P. (2009). The propositional nature of human associative learning. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 32(2), 183–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1969). On the nature of certain philosophical entities. The Monist, 53(2), 159–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, A. (forthcoming). Mindless accuracy. Synthese.

  • Morgan, C. (1894). An introduction to comparative psychology. London: Walter Scott.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, A., & Piccinini, G. (2017). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of intentionality. Minds and Machines, 28(1), 119–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, S. (1978). Fundamental aspects of cognitive representation. In E. Rosch & B. Bloom-Lloyd (Eds.), Cognition and Categorization (pp. 259–303). Lawrence: Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1992). Scenarios, concepts and perception. In T. Crane (Ed.), The contents of experience: Essays on perception (pp. 105–135). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quartz, S., & Sejnowski, T. (1997). The neural basis of cognitive development: A constructivist manifesto. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20(5), 537–556.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rand, D., et al. (2006). Uncovering the design principles of circadian clocks: Mathematical analysis of flexibility and evolutionary goals. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 238(3), 616–635.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, P., et al. (1984). Molecular analysis of the period locus in drosophila melanogaster and identification of a transcript involved in biological rhythms. Cell, 38(3), 701–710.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz, F., & Umerez, J. (2018). Dealing with the changeable and blurry edges of living things: A modified version of property-cluster kinds. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8(3), 493–518.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salter, M., Franklin, K., & Whitelam, G. (2003). Gating of the rapid shade-avoidance response by the circadian clock in plants. Nature, 426(6967), 680–683.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, T. (2006). Reply to critics. Dialogue, 45(1), 165–174.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, A., & Koller, D. (1986). Diurnal phototropism in solar tracking leaves of lavatera cretica. Plant Physiology, 80(3), 778–781.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3(3), 417–457.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1(19), 253–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shanks, D. (2007). Associationism and cognition: Human contingency learning at 25. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 60(3), 291–309.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, R., & Chipman, S. (1970). Second-order isomorphism of internal representations: Shapes of states. Cognitive Psychology, 1(1), 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (2016). Vagueness. In Zalta, E. (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/vagueness/. Accessed November 2017.

  • Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. Syntax and Semantics, 9, 315–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1998). What might nonconceptual content be? Philosophical Issues, 9, 339–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. The Journal of Philosophy, 98(8), 411–444.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (1995). Basic minds. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 251–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. (2004). The silence of the senses. Mind, 113(449), 57–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation? The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yakir, E., Hilman, D., Harir, Y., & Green, R. (2007). Regulation of output from the plant circadian clock. FEBS Journal, 274(2), 335–345.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alex Morgan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Morgan, A. Pictures, Plants, and Propositions. Minds & Machines 29, 309–329 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-018-9483-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-018-9483-4

Keywords

Navigation