Skip to main content
Log in

The Epistemic Importance of Technology in Computer Simulation and Machine Learning

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Scientificity is essentially methodology. The use of information technology as methodological instruments in science has been increasing for decades, this raises the question: Does this transform science? This question is the subject of the Special Issue in Minds and Machines “The epistemological significance of methods in computer simulation and machine learning”. We show that there is a technological change in this area that has three methodological and epistemic consequences: methodological opacity, reproducibility issues, and altered forms of justification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cf. Poppers reconstruction: “Thus I shall try to establish the rules, or if you will the norms, by which the scientist is guided when he is engaged in research or in discovery, in the sense here understood.” (Popper 2002, p. 29).

  2. We refer mainly to his manuscripts The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology (Husserl 1970). The manuscripts on which Husserl had worked in the mid-1930s until his death in 1938 appeared posthumously. However, preliminary studies of this can already be found in the articles on renewal published in early 1920 (cf. Husserl 1989), initially in a Japanese journal.

  3. Cf. also the informative Supplement III to the Crisis-manuscript about the origin of geometry. See also Kaminski (2013).

  4. For a foundation of this understanding of technology see Hubig (2006).

  5. This means that our distinction between, intellectual, social and material technology is not intended to isolate them in separate classes. Rather, they are different aspects from which we can look at technology. Cf. Hubig (2006).

  6. For the following see chapters 4, 6–7 in Foerster (2003).

  7. Feynman suggested what it means to understand an equation. He distinguishes two ways of behaving towards mathematical equations. One is to understand them analytically, through which we gain insight into them. The second is to do the math, to compute the equation. In this case we look at the dynamics of the equations but we don’t have an insight into their structure. Cf. Feynman (2010): 2–1. Lenhard (2015, p. 99) has drawn attention to this important distinction made by Feynman.

  8. Humphreys thus opposes the position of Frigg and Reiss (2009), who argue that the questions of the philosophy of simulation can be traced back to classical questions of the philosophy of science. These considerations have been further developed by Kuorikoski (2012), Saam (2017), Grüne-Yanoff (2017), Barberousse and Vorms (2014), Symons and Alvarado (2016), Newman (2016), Lenhard (2011, 2015).

  9. With regard to the philosophy of testimony and the argument developed there that epistemology is essentially social, there is no knowledge without social opacity. Cf. Coady (1992), Faulkner (2015).

  10. Cf. Rosenfeld et al. (2018), see also Goswami et al. (2018), Kurakin et al. (2017).

References

  • Barberousse, A., & Vorms, M. (2014). About the warrants of computer-based empirical knowledge. Synthese, 191(15), 3595–3620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blumenberg, H. (1999). Lebenswelt und Technisierung unter Aspekten der Phänomenologie. Wirklichkeiten in denen wir leben. Aufsätze und eine Rede (pp. 7–54). Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coady, C. (1992). Testimony. A philosophical study. Oxford: Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faulkner, P. (2015). Knowledge on trust. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend, P. K. (1975). Against method. Outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feynman, R. P. (2010). The Feynman lectures on physics. Mainly electromagnetism and matter. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Reiss, J. (2009). The philosophy of simulation. Hot new issues or same old stew? Synthese, 169(3), 593–613.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Goswami, G., Ratha, N., Agarwal, A., Singh, R., Vatsa, M. (2018). Unravelling robustness of deep learning based face recognition against adversarial attacks. Online available: http://arxiv.org/pdf/1803.00401v1. Accessed November 22, 2018.

  • Grüne-Yanoff, T. (2017). Seven problems with massive simulation models for policy decision-making. In M. Resch, A. Kaminski, & P. Gehring (Eds.), Science and art of simulation I (SAS). Exploring—understanding—knowing (pp. 85–101). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • HPC-10 (2013). Reduzierung numerischer sensitivitäten in der crashsimulation auf HPC-rechnern. Report.

  • Hubig, C. (2006). Die Kunst des Möglichen I. Technikphilosophie als Reflexion der Medialität. Bielefeld: Transcript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2004). Extending ourselves. Computational science, empiricism, and scientific method. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2009). The philosophical novelty of computer simulation methods. Synthese, 169(3), 615–626.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology. An introduction to phenomenological philosophy. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1989). Fünf Aufsätze über Erneuerung. Aufsätze und Vorträge (1922–1937) (pp. 3–124). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, A. (2013). Husserl: Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie. In C. Hubig, A. Huning, & G. Ropohl (Eds.), Nachdenken über Technik. Die Klassiker der Technikphilosophie und neuere Entwicklungen. Darmstädter Ausgabe (pp. 186–192). Berlin: Edition Sigma.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, A., Resch, M., & Küster, U. (2018). Mathematische Opazität. Reproduzierbarkeit in der Computersimulation. Jahrbuch Technikphilosophie, 4, 253–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J. (2012). Simulation and the sense of understanding. In: Humphreys, P., & Imbert, C. (Eds.), Models, simulations, and representations (pp. 168–186). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurakin, A., Goodfellow, I., Bengio, S. (2017). Adversarial examples in the physical world. Under review as a conference paper at ICLR 2017. Online available https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Ian_Goodfellow/publication/305186613_Adversarial_examples_in_the_physical_world/links/5830d14508ae138f1c05ef15/Adversarial-examples-in-the-physical-world.pdf?origin=publication_detail. Visited 11 Nov 2018.

  • Lenhard, J. (2011). Epistemologie der Iteration Gedankenexperimente und Simulationsexperimente. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 59(1), 131–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard, J. (2015). Mit allem rechnen—zur Philosophie der Computersimulation. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, J. (2016). Epistemic opacity, confirmation holism and technical debt: Computer simulation in the light of empirical software engineering. In: Gadducci, F., & Tavosanis, M. (Eds.), History and philosophy of computing (pp. 256–272). Cham: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (2002). The logic of scientific discovery. London, New York: Routledge

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenfeld, A., Zemel, R., Tsotsos, J.K. (2018). The elephant in the room. Online available http://arxiv.org/pdf/1808.03305v1. Visited 11 Nov 2018.

  • Saam, N. (2017). Understanding social science simulations. Distinguishing two categories of simulations. In M. Resch, A. Kaminski, & P. Gehring (Eds.), Science and art of simulation I (SAS) Exploring—understanding—knowing (pp. 67–84). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schappals, M., Mecklenfeld, A., Kröger, L., Botan, V., Köster, A., Stephan, S., et al. (2017). Round robin study: Molecular simulation of thermodynamic properties from models with internal degrees of freedom. Journal of Chemical Theory and Computation, 13(9), 4270–4280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Symons, J., & Alvarado, R. (2016) Can we trust Big Data? Applying philosophy of science to software. Big Data and Society, 3(2), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Foerster, H. (2003). Understanding understanding. Essays on cybernetics and cognition. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael Resch.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Resch, M., Kaminski, A. The Epistemic Importance of Technology in Computer Simulation and Machine Learning. Minds & Machines 29, 9–17 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-019-09496-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-019-09496-5

Keywords

Navigation