Skip to main content
Log in

On physicalism and Downward Causation in Developmental and Cancer Biology

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Acta Biotheoretica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The dominant position in Philosophy of Science contends that downward causation is an illusion. Instead, we argue that downward causation doesn’t introduce vicious circles either in physics or in biology. We also question the metaphysical claim that “physical facts fix all the facts.” Downward causation does not imply any contradiction if we reject the assumption of the completeness and the causal closure of the physical world that this assertion contains. We provide an argument for rejecting this assumption. Furthermore, this allows us to reconsider the concept of diachronic emergence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “The skyhook concept is perhaps a descendant of the deus ex machina of ancient Greek dramaturgy: when second-rate playwrights found their plots leading their heroes into inescapable difficulties they were often tempted to crank down a god into the scene, like Superman, to save the situation supernaturally” (Dennett 1996: 74).

  2. “That is, we interpret the hierarchical levels as levels of concepts and descriptions, or levels within our representational apparatus, rather than levels of properties and phenomena in the world”.

  3. Normally, “substrate neutrality” and “supervenience” are not compatible with a strong reductionism, since supervenient properties cannot be deduced form physical ones: “no actual derivation may be effected, owing to the famous “many-one” relation between the physical supervenience base and the biological properties to which the PNS adverts” (Rosenberg and Kaplan 2005).

  4. A system of molecules will assume in a long period of time all conceivable microstates that are compatible with the conservation of energy.

  5. The origin of this idea is in Feibleman (1954), see also Stengers (1997).

  6. “The same notion of a God’-Eye View”… the same epistemic ideal of achieving a view from an “Archimedean point”—a point from which we can survey observers as if they were not ourselves, survey them as if we were, so to speak, outside of our own skins—is involved” (Putnam 1990: 17).

  7. (Putnam 1990: 17).

  8. Differentiation: the sum of the developmental processes whereby from a single cell, the zygote the organism attains the diverse adult structures (cells, tissues and organs) and functions.

  9. Epithelium: an avascular tissue that covers a free surface or lines-up a tube or cavity in an animal body and serves especially to enclose and protect the other parts of the body, produces secretions and excretions, and functions in assimilation (modified from: http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/mplusdictionary.html).

  10. Stroma: the supporting framework of an animal organ consisting of connective tissue (http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/mplusdictionary.html).

  11. Parenchyma: the distinctive tissue of an organ or an abnormal growth as distinguished from its supportive framework (modified from: http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/mplusdictionary.html).

  12. Basement membrane: a thin extracellular supporting layer that separates a layer of epithelial cells from the underlying lamina propria and is composed of the basal lamina and reticular lamina; Lamina propria: a highly vascular layer of connective tissue under the basement membrane lining a layer of epithelium (http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/mplusdictionary.html).

  13. Hemidesmosomes: a specialization of the plasma membrane of an epithelial cell that serves to connect the basal surface of the cell to the basement membrane (modified from: http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/mplusdictionary.html).

  14. Organelles: literally, organelle means “little organ”; they are specialized cellular parts (as a mitochondrion or ribosome) that perform the metabolic and synthetic functions of a cell.

  15. Mesenchyme: loosely organized mesodermal embryonic tissue that give rise to connective tissues (modified from: http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/mplusdictionary.html).

  16. Gastrulation: after fertilization a series of rapid mitotic divisions (cleavage) result in the blastula. Next, the process of gastrulation takes place, whereby cells change positions with respect to each other; as the result of this process the germ layers (ectoderm, mesoderm and endoderm) are formed.

  17. Drosophila: a genus of small dipteran flies that include several (as D. melanogaster) that are extensively used in genetic research (modified from: http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/mplusdictionary.html).

  18. Mesoderm: the middle of the three primary germ layers of an embryo that is the source especially of bone, muscle, connective tissue, and dermis; broadly speaking, tissue derived from this germ layer (modified from http://www.nlm.nih.gov/medlineplus/mplusdictionary.html).

  19. Germ band: a collection of cells along the ventral midline that includes all the cells that will form the trunk of the embryo (http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/books/bv.fcgi?indexed=google&rid=dbio.section.1959).

  20. ‘Time is what makes itself and even what makes everything [else] make itself.’

References

  • Bunge M (2003) Emergence and convergence. Toronto University Press

  • Cairns-Smith G (1982) Genetic takeover and the mineral origin of life. Cambridge University Press

  • Coleman W, Wennerberg AE, Smith GJ, Grisham JW (1997) Regulation of the differentiation of diploid and aneuploid rat liver epithelial (stem-like) cells by the liver microenvironment. Am J Pathol 142:1373–1382

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (1996) Darwin’s dangerous idea. Touchstone, NewYork

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobhzansky Th (1973) Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. Am Biol Teach 35:125–129

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem P (1906) La Théorie physique, son Objet, sa Structure. Chevalier et Rivière, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Farge E (2003) Mechanical induction of twist in the Drosophila foregut/stomodeal primordium. Curr Biol 13:1365–1377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feibleman JK (1954) Theory of integrative levels. Br J Philos Sci 5(17):59–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R (1930) The genetical theory of natural selection. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert S (1997) Developmental biology, 5th edn. Sinauer Associates, Inc., Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendrix MJ, Seftor EA, Seftor RE, Kasemeier-Kulesa J, Kulesa PM, Postovit LM (2007) Reprogramming metastatic tumour cells with embryonic microenvironments. Nat Rev Cancer 4:246–255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman S (2000) Investigations. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim J (1993) Supervenience and mind. Cambridge University Press

  • Kim J (1998) Philosophy of mind. Westview Press

  • Kim J (1999) Making sense of emergence. Philos Stud 95:3–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1984) 1953 and all that: a tale of two sciences. Philos Rev 93:335–373

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longo G, Bailly F (2006) Mathématiques et Sciences de la Nature. La singularité physique du vivant, Hermann, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Maffini MV, Soto AM, Calabro JM, Ucci AA, Sonnenschein C (2004) The stroma as a crucial target in rat mammary gland carcinogenesis. J Cell Sci 117:1495–1502

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maffini MV, Calabro JM, Soto AM, Sonnenschein C (2005) Stromal regulation of neoplastic development: age-dependent normalization of neoplastic mammary cells by mammary stroma. Am J Pathol 67:1405–1410

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E (1961) Cause and effect in biology. Nature 134:1501–1505

    Google Scholar 

  • Mintz B, Ilmensee K (1975) Normal genetically mosaic mice produced from malignant teratocarcinoma cells. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 72:3585–3589

    Google Scholar 

  • Noble D (2006) The music of life. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Perovic S (2007) The limitation of Kim’s reductive physicalism. Acta Biotheor 55:243–267

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1990) Realism as a human face. Harvard University Press

  • Rosenberg A, Kaplan DM (2005) How to reconcile physicalism and antireductionism about biology. Philos Sci 72:43–68

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakakura T, Sakagami Y, Nishizuka Y (1979) Persistence of responsiveness of adult mouse mammary gland to induction by embryonic mesenchyme. Dev Biol 72:201–210

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sievers D, Von Kiedrovski G (1994) Self-replication of complementary nucleotide-based oligomers. Nature 369:221–224

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smola H, Stark H-J, Gabi Thiekötter G, Mirancea N, Krieg T, Fusenig NE (1998) Dynamics of basement membrane formation by keratinocyte–fibroblast interactions. In: Organotypic skin culture. Exp Cell Res 239:399–410

  • Sonnenschein C, Soto A (1999) The society of cells. Bios Scientific Publishers, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Soto A, Sonnenschein C (2004) Emergentism as a default: cancer as a problem of tissue organization. J Biosci 30:103–118

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stengers I (1997) Cosmopolitiques VI. La découverte, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen B (1989) Laws and symmetry. Oxford University Press

  • Van Fraassen B (1999) The manifest image and the scientific image. In: Aerts D (ed) Einstein meets Magritte: the white book—an interdisciplinary reflection. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 29–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann J (1961) The general and logical theory of automata. In: Taub AH (ed) John von Neumann: collected works. Volume V: design of computers, theory of automata and numerical analysis, vol 9. Pergamon Press, Oxford, pp 288–328

  • Wright S (1932) The roles of mutation, inbreeding, crossbreeding, and selection. In: Jones DF (ed) Evolution. Proceedings of the sixth international congress of genetics, pp 356–366

  • Wright S (1977) Evolution and the genetics of population, T3. University Chicago Press, Chicago

  • Wright S (1980) Genic and organismic selection. Evolution 34:825–843

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Professor Ulises Moulines (University of Munich) and Doctor Slobodan Perovic (Carleton University) for their critical reading and helpful comments concerning an earlier draft of this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to P. A. Miquel.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Soto, A.M., Sonnenschein, C. & Miquel, P.A. On physicalism and Downward Causation in Developmental and Cancer Biology. Acta Biotheor 56, 257–274 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-008-9052-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-008-9052-y

Keywords

Navigation