Abstract

BACKGROUND

Prenatal diagnosis based on different technologies is increasingly used in developed countries and has become a common strategy in obstetric practice. The tests are crucial in enabling mothers to make informed decisions about the possibility of terminating pregnancy. They have generated numerous bioethical and legal controversies in the field of ‘wrongful life’ claims (action brought by or on behalf of a child against the mother or other people, claiming that he or she has to endure a not-worth-living existence) and ‘wrongful birth’ claims (action brought by the mother or parents against the physician for being burdened with an unwanted, often disabled child, which could have been avoided).

OBJECTIVE AND RATIONALE

The possibility which exists nowadays to intervene actively by programming and deciding the phases linked to procreation and birth has raised several questions worldwide. The mother's right to self-determination could be an end but whether or not this right is absolute is debatable. Freedom could, with time, act as a barrier that obstructs intrusion into other people's lives and their personal choices. Therapeutic choices may be manageable in a liberal sense, and the sanctity of life can be inflected in a secular sense. These sensitive issues and the various points of view to be considered have motivated this review.

SEARCH METHODS

Literature searches were conducted on relevant demographic, social science and medical science databases (SocINDEX, Econlit, PopLine, Medline, Embase and Current Contents) and via other sources. Searches focused on subjects related to bioethical and legal controversies in the field of preimplantation and prenatal diagnosis, wrongful birth and wrongful life. A review of the international state of law was carried out, focusing attention on the peculiar issue of wrongful life and investigating the different jurisdictional solutions of wrongful life claims in a comparative survey.

OUTCOMES

Courts around the world are generally reluctant to acknowledge wrongful life claims due to their ethical and legal implications, such as existence as an injury, the right not to be born, the nature of the harm suffered and non-existence as an alternative to a disabled life. Most countries have rejected such actions while at the same time approving those for wrongful birth. Some countries, such as France with a law passed in March 2002, have definitively excluded Wrongful Life action. Only in the Netherlands and in three states of the USA (California, Washington and New Jersey) Wrongful Life actions are allowed. In other countries, such as Belgium, legislation is unclear because, despite a first decision of the Court allowing Wrongful Life action, the case is still in progress. There is a complete lack of case law regarding wrongful conception, wrongful birth and wrongful life in a few countries, such as Estonia.

WIDER IMPLICATIONS

The themes of ‘wrongful birth’ and ‘wrongful life’ are charged with perplexing ethical dilemmas and raise delicate legal questions. These have met, in various countries and on certain occasions, with different solutions and have triggered ethical and juridical debate. The damage case scenarios result from a lack of information or diagnosis prior to the birth, which deprives the mother of the chance to terminate the pregnancy.

Introduction

Prenatal diagnosis (PD) using different technologies (foetal ultrasonography, genetic screening, laboratory tests, etc.) is increasingly used to explore the health and genetic conditions of unborn children and to inform expectant mothers of potential foetal anomalies and diseases that may create physical, psychological, and social harm to parents and families. In developed countries, there has been truly outstanding progress in prenatal diagnostic methods. These, however, have generated numerous bioethical and legal controversies and issues (Pelias, 1986; Strong, 2003; Crockin, 2005; Chervenak and McCullough, 2011; Amagwula et al., 2012; Chadwick and Childs, 2012; Berceanu et al., 2014; de Jong et al., 2015; Dondorp and van Lith, 2015).

When introduced, prenatal investigations such as invasive genetic diagnosis (Druzin et al., 1993), second-trimester ultrasound screening (Chervenak et al., 1989), and first-trimester risk assessment (Chasen et al., 2001) appeared controversial. They have since, however, become common strategies in obstetric practice (Ewigman et al., 1990; Wald, 2002; O'Brien et al., 2015).

Several parties are directly involved in prenatal diagnostic practice, i.e. the mother/parents, the foetus or newborn and finally the perinatal medicine practitioners.

Unlike the majority of diagnostic activities in medicine, the conditions, in most cases, cannot be cured or alleviated. Following an undesired result, the only option therefore is to decide whether to accept the child's condition and prepare for the birth or to terminate the pregnancy (Gekas et al., 2016). Consequently, the main reason for offering prenatal genetic testing is to enhance the reproductive autonomy of the woman and/or couple with regard to parenting or preventing the birth of a child with a serious disorder or disability (DiSilvestro, 2009; Schmitz et al., 2009; Wright and Chitty, 2009; Deans et al., 2015; Wilkinson, 2015). In other words, PD technologies are crucial to enable mothers to make an informed decision as to whether or not to terminate the pregnancy (Hewison, 2015).

From another point of view, the duty to give appropriate information in order to obtain informed consent is placed on the medical professionals. The question, in fact, arises as to whether or not physicians are obliged: to disclose the availability of prenatal tests to eligible patients as part of the physician–patient discussion about prenatal screening and diagnosis, to explain the risk of false-positive and false-negative test results and the uncertain implications of results and finally, to fully inform the patient about the results of the tests themselves. It is presumed that new medical techniques in the area of prenatal testing are used to give a pregnant patient as much information as possible concerning the health of her foetus. What course of action is taken thereafter is left entirely up to the patient and is essentially a personal choice. Giving the mother/parents the opportunity to make such a decision based on all of the available, accurate information is the primary responsibility of the prenatal counsellor. If an error occurs in giving or interpreting the test, the physician may be faced with an extremely delicate situation, engaging his/her moral and legal responsibility. Mothers/parents who seek prenatal counselling expect to receive accurate information regarding the health of the foetus. If they are reassured by a medical practitioner as to the health of the foetus and the child is subsequently born with an anomaly or disease, the parents have effectively been deprived of their right to make an informed decision about whether to terminate or continue the pregnancy. Failure may occur by omission or failed communication of pertinent information to the parents or by an alleged error in the interpretation of the diagnostic information (Klein and Mahoney, 2007; Frati et al., 2014; Toews and Caulfield, 2014).

In this article, we firstly explore the bioethical debate surrounding the issue of preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) and PD. We then focus on the peculiar issues of wrongful birth and wrongful life, investigating the different jurisdictional solutions of wrongful life claims in a comparative survey, and laying bare some of the ethical issues involved. Finally, the ethical views regarding these controversial matters are delineated. This review suggests new frontiers for obstetric decision-making.

When we discuss maternal and foetal interests in an ethical context, one of the most critical issues is that of balancing the mother's right to self-determination and autonomy with the best interests of the unborn child (Munthe, 2015). Ethical dilemmas arise from what are often described as ‘maternal–foetal conflicts’ (Mahowald, 1993; Steinbock, 1994).

Firstly, as part of the bioethical debate underlines, this locution perpetuates the premise that the foetus, like the pregnant woman, is a person, whose interests and rights must be protected (Flagler et al., 1997). Again, the expression ‘maternal–foetal conflicts’ evokes an opposition between maternal and foetal rights and seems to imply that the nature and status of the foetus are not in doubt.

Upon birth, a baby is considered to acquire both moral and legal standing as a separate person. However, prior to birth, does the foetus have independent interests from the mother? Can it claim rights against its mother? Foetal rights doctrines grant implicit legal status to the unborn child, assuming that the foetus is a full human being from the moment of conception. Other opposing positions accord the foetus no moral or legal standing (Isaacs, 2003). Only if the foetus is considered a person, can rights and conflicts with another person, like the mother, arise. There can be no conflict without rights (Yeo and Lim, 2011). What constitutes a right is a further complex question (Savulescu, 2002; Hafner, 2011). If we assume that the foetus is a person and that foetal rights exist, women's and foetal rights may be difficult to reconcile, making it possible for the rights of a zygote, embryo or foetus to trump those of a pregnant woman in certain circumstances (Uberoi and de Bruyn, 2013). Taking the opposite view, others argue that a foetus has no moral status independent of its mother (Isaacs, 2003).

In this context, we believe that it is critical to distinguish between the legal and moral rights of the foetus and the concept of ‘best interest’ of both mother and unborn child. In making the complex link between rights and interests, it could be stressed that rights protect interests (Savulescu, 2002). An example immediately comes to mind, the right not to be born would exists if a child had an interest in not being born (Jecker, 2012). In the framework of ethical dilemmas that arise during pregnancy, some argue that there can be opposition between maternal and foetal rights, as the autonomy and self-determination of most women may conflict with the ‘best interest of the foetus’. If, in recent decades, respect for the autonomy and self-determination of all people (including pregnant women) has become an accepted ethical principle in every field of medicine, it appears to be inextricably linked with the principle of beneficence (and that of non-maleficence), presuming that everyone (pregnant woman, couples and physicians) act in the best interests of the foetus. In general, we can say that the pregnant woman makes decisions that are ‘in the interests’ of the foetus and, prospectively, of the child (Jonsen, 1988; Watt, 2016). However, in some circumstances, the principle of respect for the pregnant woman's autonomy may collide with the principles of beneficence and/or non-maleficence toward the foetus. Once again, principles are difficult to reconcile, and it is essential to avoid the risk of fulfilling a moral obligation of beneficence towards the foetus at the expense of maternal autonomy. Our personal view is that alleged foetal rights cannot be elevated over the rights of the pregnant woman and that the woman's autonomy and right to self-determination should override the ‘rights’ and interests of her foetus, provided she is fully and adequately informed and competent to make a decision.

Methods

Literature searches were conducted on relevant demographic, social science and medical science databases (SocINDEX, Econlit, PopLine, Medline, Embase and Current Contents) and via other sources. Searches focused on subjects related to bioethical and legal controversies in the field of PGD and PD, wrongful birth and wrongful life. A review of the international state of law was carried out, focusing attention on the peculiar issue of wrongful life and investigating the different jurisdictional solutions of wrongful life and birth claims in a comparative survey.

PGD: bioethical considerations

The constant evolution of scientific progress has permitted us to exceed the boundaries of what was once considered the natural cycle of life, posing several ethical dilemmas that are not easy to solve (Kushnir et al., 2016). Intervening actively, by planning and deciding the phases linked to procreation and birth, is nowadays possible (Dondorp and de Wert, 2011; Hens et al., 2013; Harper et al., 2014). These are complex times in which the rights of the couple are intertwined with the rights of the foetus, with the interests of each connected in various ways to planned parenthood and ultimately to the attainment of life, but only on certain conditions. The legitimate expectations of becoming parents are balanced against the greater or lesser protection, often unsuccessful, of an entity that is not yet a person. The ethical and legal debate is intense and in continuous evolution, and in tension with the attribution of individual control and widespread acknowledgement of the principle of self-determination.

Procreation and birth introduce responsibilities that were once not even imaginable, obliging the judge and the ethicist to modify their attitudes to, if not life itself, at least the quality of life. With prenatal screening and even more so, preimplantation diagnosis, the decision, to become parents no matter what or instead to subordinate this desire to the birth of a healthy child, is left to the parents themselves. In the absence of well-defined legislation, which would be the preferable option, it is important to at least reach, if possible, a shared ethical decision with a scale of values that can guide the lawfulness of choices (Dondorp and van Lith, 2015; Lowther et al., 2015; Wasserman, 2015).

The suffering and hardships that a disabled life entails can be rejected by preventing the birth event itself. They could also be alleviated through compensation, thus attributing the responsibility to others. But who is able to evaluate the quality of life of someone born with a disability? And therefore, who can legitimately initiate legal proceedings in order to obtain relief? These are just some of the many questions raised by the issue of prenatal and preimplantation diagnosis.

In today's society, there is a widespread feeling that it is not life that should be protected at all costs, but the quality of life. This view would seem to be in direct opposition to the concept of the ‘sanctity of life’. Consequently, the approach to such a delicate issue cannot disregard the sensitivity underlying those ethical values which should serve as coordinates. These issues have been the matter of a lively doctrinal, regulatory and juridical debate all over the world (Molinelli et al., 2012; Propping and Schott, 2014; Brezina and Kutteh, 2015; de Jong and de Wert, 2015).

The possibility of carrying out PGD for couples who have resorted to assisted reproduction has been a matter of debate in several countries (Boggio and Corbellini, 2009). This practice consists in the collection of cell samples from the embryo before its implantation in the mother's womb in order to verify its state of health and, above all, the presence of any genetic disorders (Gulino et al., 2013; Zuradzki, 2014; Durland, 2015; Hu et al., 2015; Capalbo et al. 2016; Chang et al. 2016; Irion and Irion, 2016). In several countries, including Italy, the right to preimplantation diagnosis, for couples who had resorted to in vitro fertilization techniques, was not recognized from the start (Turillazzi and Fineschi, 2008; Busardò et al., 2014; Turillazzi et al., 2015). In several cases, besides the prohibition of any kind of preimplantation diagnosis for eugenic purposes, it has been stressed that any investigations carried out should be ‘observational’. This, then, rules out invasive studies, such as those that involve the collection of cell samples.

Such positions have fuelled the debate, in particular, on the balancing of interests between the protection of the embryo on the one hand and, on the other, the protection of the mother's health and the couple's right to know the state of health of the embryo itself. In particular, it may be debatable to prohibit the assessment of possible anomalies or genetic disorders through an investigation of the embryo which is not yet implanted in the womb while legalizing the PD of the foetus. The latter procedure is clearly more aggressive than preimplantation genetic diagnosis and may lead to the termination of pregnancy, which may be both physically painful and mentally distressing for the mother.

Recently, however, there has been a tendency to recognize the parents’ right to access preimplantation diagnosis techniques.

Among the most important arguments raised in this respect, it is worth mentioning: (i) the parents’ right to be informed as to the state of health of the embryo to be implanted, in accordance with the general principle of informed consent required for all medical treatment; (ii) the necessity to protect the mother's right to health since the implantation of a malformed embryo or of one carrying genetic disorders cannot only cause psychological distress to the mother but could also increase the risk of pregnancy complications or miscarriage; and (iii) the problematic nature of the ban on PGD, in view of the mother's right to carry out genetic analysis and diagnosis on the already formed foetus (through the amniocentesis and chorionic villus sampling techniques) and subsequently to interrupt pregnancy.

Undoubtedly, the application of PGD raises controversial and highly debated ethical problems (Robertson, 2003, 2005; De Wert, 2005; Soini et al., 2006; Basille et al., 2009; Hens et al., 2013; De Wert, et al., 2014; Whetstine, 2015). Aside from the moral status of the embryo, debates concerning the acceptability of PGD have included the potential biological impact as well as moral, political and religious values. It should be borne in mind that ethical concerns relating to PGD are strictly intertwined with religious values and beliefs, cultural and social backgrounds, and lived experience and emotions (Gebhart et al., 2016). As in other fields of predictive prenatal medicine, heterogeneous positions may exist, depending on whether a human being, defined as a person, is considered as coming into existence at the time of fertilization or as gradually acquiring the full status of a human being during intrauterine development.

In this regard, similarities and differences can be drawn with regard to PD. For those who believe that the foetus is not a person, there seem to be differences in the ethical justification between the two procedures, PGD and PD. PGD may be psychologically less distressing for the mother and the couple who may feel more detached from an embryo on a Petri dish compared to a foetus growing inside the womb. In the same way, for those who attribute moral status to the embryo, both PGD and PD are unacceptable. With this hypothesis, there are also slight differences between the two procedures: one might argue, for example that in PGD the ethical disvalue can be greater because more embryos are created, by assisted procreation methods, and then destroyed while, in general, in PD followed by an abortion, only one foetus is aborted. Yet again, since a moral value can be attributed to pregnancy itself, some might consider PGD to be ethically more acceptable than PD since, in the former, the pregnancy has not yet begun (Cameron and Williamson, 2003; Bartha et al., 2006).

It has been said that PGD is morally singular due to the fact that patients and clinicians are involved in creating a new life, which also entails responsibility for the welfare of the future child (Hens et al., 2013). PGD is a part of the complex debate surrounding ‘procreative beneficence’ that states that if selection of an embryo is reasonably possible, then couples have a moral obligation to select the embryo whose life can be expected to be the best quality (Savulescu, 2001, 2007; Savulescu and Kahane, 2009; Rodriguez-Purata et al., 2015). This concept in itself, has raised many ethical controversies (Bennett, 2014; Petersen, 2015). Furthermore, from the advantages of predictive medicine to the risk of genetic discrimination, choices may become more and more difficult and controversial (Aurenque, 2015; Mertes and Hens, 2015). From the standpoint of ethical speculation, there are many points of discussion. The ethical and moral acceptability of PGD, which has a specific burden (e.g. risk of eventual embryo loss and costs of the procedure), may depend on the benefit of avoiding the conception of an affected child. In other words, diagnosis and genetic selection in order to avoid serious and potentially fatal (or seriously disabling) genetically determined diseases (where there is a high risk of serious diseases) may sound ethically differently from PGD for mutations in genes that merely increase the risk (without a guarantee that the condition will develop later) of less severe conditions or cause a carrier status for recessive disorders, or for sex selection for indirect medical reasons (an application often considered ‘eugenic’) (de Wert et al., 2014; Altarescu et al., 2015). There may be general agreement on the acceptability of the so-called medical model of PGD (deWert, 2002; Steinbock, 2002), when it focuses on and is restricted to the diagnosis of (future) health problems, more precisely aberrations/mutations which (may) affect the health of the prospective child, but it still remains ethically troublesome (McMahan, 2005).

Worries about the possible negative effects of the use of PGD on disabled people do exist on the grounds that it is discriminatory, has pernicious effects on the lives of disabled people, and expresses a hurtful view of disability (Parens and Asch, 2003; Malek, 2010). Some claim that even preventing the birth of severely disabled children using PGD is morally unacceptable (Petersen, 2005), predicting that the use of PD technologies will lead to more injustice and greater discrimination against people with disabilities, negatively affecting our perception and care of children who are born disabled.

Concerns and worries about the consequences of PGD technologies may become even more exacerbated when applied for the selection of desirable non-medical traits unrelated to health, such as intelligence, height, hair or eye colour, beauty or athletic genotypes (so-called ‘designer babies’) or when applied for the possibility offered, and obtainable by means of PGD, of conceiving healthy children to save the life of another diseased child (El-Toukhy et al., 2011). Even more debatable are the exceptional requests by couples who themselves are affected by a genetic disease (deafness, dwarfism by achondroplasia) to perform PGD and select embryos carrying the same mutation for transfer to the uterus. The International Bioethics Committee of UNESCO considers such an approach to be unethical because it does not take into account the many lifelong and irreversible disadvantages that will burden the future person.

Prenatal diagnosis

PD is one of the areas of medicine to receive a great deal of attention in recent years, both in the scientific and bioethical fields (Strong, 2003; Chervenak and McCullough, 2011; Chadwick and Childs, 2012; Berceanu et al., 2014; de Jong et al., 2015; Dondorp and van Lith, 2015). Interest has been fuelled by surprising and constant progress in the field and by inherent bioethical problems. Increasingly accurate prenatal tests and investigations give parents powerful tools for gleaning information about their unborn offspring (Brezina and Kearns, 2014). However, scientific progress in this field undoubtedly raises ethical challenges (Sijmons et al., 2011).

Before discussing the peculiar issue of wrongful life that derives from PD development, it is necessary to try to define the bioethical presuppositions that underlie PD in general.

The term PD refers to techniques that allow the diagnosis of several diseases of the human embryo or foetus. Although PD potentially allows targeted diagnostic testing for the planning of the delivery, the counselling and education of the couples, and early postnatal interventions for newborns with congenital malformations (Lakhoo, 2012), it also often detects severe abnormalities where treatment is unavailable or unlikely to be successful, and where the death of the foetus or neonate is a likely outcome. One of the options available to mothers (and couples) when a severe or lethal disease is detected is the termination of the pregnancy (Menahem and Grimwade, 2003; Athanasiadis et al., 2009; Kose et al., 2015; Maxwell et al., 2015; Domröse et al., 2016; Gaille, 2016).

Thus, the central issue is related to the status of the human embryo or foetus. The first problem is to define the human embryo or foetus. It is beyond the scope of this article to provide a detailed discussion of the bioethical and philosophical debate that has developed in our society surrounding the actual beginning of human life, which has always been viewed differently by various individuals, groups, cultures and religions (Dunstan, 1984; Shea, 1985; Beller and Zlatnik, 1992, 1995; Drgonec, 1994; Shannon, 1997; Reuter, 2000; Kurjak and Tripalo, 2003; Schenker, 2008; Benagiano et al., 2011; Ventura-Juncá and Santos, 2011). A question in the ongoing multidisciplinary debate is whether the life of an embryo could be considered similar to that of a human being. If so, from conception onwards, the same protection allowed to every human is also due for the embryo. Other positions consider that respect for the human life is conditioned by the level of its development. Over the years, these different positions have animated a lively debate on issues such as abortion. In recent years, the issue has acquired a new dimension due to our growing capacity to make diagnoses at the beginning of life in ways that could not have been anticipated some decades ago. As has been argued, these technologies have redefined the scale, scope and the boundaries of medicine (Webster, 2002).

In this paradigm, the first step is to pay particular attention to the ‘therapeutic’ indications for PD. Questions arise, such as ‘is there a treatment that is reasonably expected to benefit the patient?’, ‘are there side adverse effects?’ and ‘are these negative effects tolerable in the light of the expected benefits?’. Motives behind PD may vary from the prevention, healing and/or alleviation of diseases to allowing people (mother/parents) to make procreative informed decisions in accordance with their own values and view of life. If only the former motive is accepted, PD should only be carried out when the foetus with the disease or abnormality could potentially benefit from the available therapeutic measures. In recent years, advances in prenatal screening and diagnosis mean that the majority of genetic diseases can be detected early in gestation (Beaudet, 2015). Early diagnosis provides the option of possible treatment. Surgical foetal interventions, and especially prenatal stem cell and gene therapy, have the potential to treat a broad range of congenital disorders (Loukogeorgakis and Flake, 2014; McClain and Flake, 2016). However, the clinical scenario varies from foetal treatment with a reasonable chances of success, to experimental foetal therapy with a low chance of success, thus raising profound ethical issues (Dickens and Cook, 2003; Chervenak and McCullough, 2007; Noble and Rodeck, 2008; Dickens and Cook, 2011; Ville, 2011; Chadwick and Childs, 2012; Munson, 1975; McMann et al., 2014).

When PD leads to prenatal treatment, which may involve invasive procedures, this may put the pregnant woman's health at risk. Furthermore, complications such as premature birth cannot be overlooked. This brings into question the appropriateness of carrying out risky procedures for the uncertain possibility of benefit to the foetus and the possible conflict between maternal and foetal health. In such circumstances, the pregnant woman is asked to make decisions about her own medical care that unavoidably involves the health, prognosis and even the possibility of survival of her unborn child. Women themselves might find it difficult to decide for or against treatment. As a consequence, underlying issues are at stake: the responsibility of healthcare providers towards the mother and foetus and the duty to give appropriate information and advice to pregnant women (Hunt et al., 2005). The pregnant woman should be given all the information regarding the potential benefit and risk to the foetus, and to her own health and fertility.

Summing up, the ethical debate surrounding PD, some conflicting key points may be drawn.

For those for whom the human embryo should be considered a living being from conception onwards, PD can be justified when the option exists for therapeutic action on the foetus. The right of parents to be informed of the health status of the foetus may be another point to eventually be counterbalanced with the best interests of the foetus. Parents have the right to be informed so as to be able to adjust their expectations for their child in the face of the child's medical prognosis. Accurate information about their child and their child's condition may be a critical step in the adaptation process that accompanies the birth of a disabled or chronically ill newborn. However, in such cases, there is also potential conflict between the autonomy of the mother to accept or refuse these treatments and the rights and interests of the foetus, as well as the question of the degree to which the mother's choices should be respected. Mothers are called on to act as ‘moral agents’ in relation to choices for the foetus (Noble and Rodeck, 2008). As a consequence, the mother also has the right to refuse treatment, irrespective of foetal viability borders (Deprest et al., 2011). In other words, if the status of person is assigned to the foetus, both the interest of the foetus and the mother should be considered, and the beneficence-based obligation to the foetus must be balanced with the beneficence-based and autonomy-based obligations to the mother.

An alternative way of looking at the issue is to consider that the aim of PD is to enable mothers and parents to make informed decisions regarding the possibility or risk of having a child with a congenital disorder, with the alternative being termination of pregnancy. Those who take the position that the human foetus before birth does not deserve absolute protection, will justify PD even when there is no therapy possible, and termination of pregnancy may be the only alternative to giving birth to a child with a congenital disease.

Wrongful birth: the conceptual paradigm

Advances in PD open the floodgates to allegations of liability for so-called ‘wrongful birth’ or ‘wrongful life’ (Roth, 2007; Pioro et al., 2008). For many years now, as the number of tests has expanded, so too has the number of lawsuits alleging negligence against the medical profession (Grady, 1992; Capen, 1995; Fisher and Witty, 2001).

Here we draw the distinguishing line between wrongful birth and wrongful life (Table I). The term ‘wrongful birth’ refers to claims for alleged negligence where an opportunity has been lost to parents to terminate a pregnancy. These claims are often related to undetected foetal abnormalities and involve a claim for damages by the parents of a child for, most importantly, the costs of bringing up the child. Other types of damages are non-pecuniary losses for both the mother and the father for interference with family life (Brantley, 1976; Botkin, 1988; Botkin and Mehlman, 1994; Whitney and Rosenbaum, 2011; Hassan et al., 2014).

Table I

Wrongful life versus wrongful birth actions.

Wrongful lifeWrongful birth
ActionClaim brought by or on behalf of a child.Claim brought by the parents.
ClaimsThe child has suffered from birth defects because the doctor is responsible for the undesired life.
  • The parents of a child born with birth defects, because of medical malpractice, were deprived of the opportunity to decide whether to terminate the pregnancy.

  • Self-determination of the mother was undermined.

  • There was a lack of information or understanding by mother/parents regarding the potential risks of having children with genetic or congenital anomalies, particularly in light of developments in prenatal diagnosis.

Damages
  • A life of pain and suffering of the child himself.

  • Costs for the maintenance of the disabled life.

  • Costs for the maintenance of the disabled child.

  • Impossibility of freely deciding their own family context.

  • Moral and psychological suffering.

ReferencesKearl (1983), Kelly (1991), Jackson (1995), Gillon (1998), Giesen (2012), Gur (2014).Lenke and Nemes (1985), Jackson (1995), Sullivan (2000), Pioro et al. (2008), Hassan et al. (2014), Hensel (2005).
Wrongful lifeWrongful birth
ActionClaim brought by or on behalf of a child.Claim brought by the parents.
ClaimsThe child has suffered from birth defects because the doctor is responsible for the undesired life.
  • The parents of a child born with birth defects, because of medical malpractice, were deprived of the opportunity to decide whether to terminate the pregnancy.

  • Self-determination of the mother was undermined.

  • There was a lack of information or understanding by mother/parents regarding the potential risks of having children with genetic or congenital anomalies, particularly in light of developments in prenatal diagnosis.

Damages
  • A life of pain and suffering of the child himself.

  • Costs for the maintenance of the disabled life.

  • Costs for the maintenance of the disabled child.

  • Impossibility of freely deciding their own family context.

  • Moral and psychological suffering.

ReferencesKearl (1983), Kelly (1991), Jackson (1995), Gillon (1998), Giesen (2012), Gur (2014).Lenke and Nemes (1985), Jackson (1995), Sullivan (2000), Pioro et al. (2008), Hassan et al. (2014), Hensel (2005).
Table I

Wrongful life versus wrongful birth actions.

Wrongful lifeWrongful birth
ActionClaim brought by or on behalf of a child.Claim brought by the parents.
ClaimsThe child has suffered from birth defects because the doctor is responsible for the undesired life.
  • The parents of a child born with birth defects, because of medical malpractice, were deprived of the opportunity to decide whether to terminate the pregnancy.

  • Self-determination of the mother was undermined.

  • There was a lack of information or understanding by mother/parents regarding the potential risks of having children with genetic or congenital anomalies, particularly in light of developments in prenatal diagnosis.

Damages
  • A life of pain and suffering of the child himself.

  • Costs for the maintenance of the disabled life.

  • Costs for the maintenance of the disabled child.

  • Impossibility of freely deciding their own family context.

  • Moral and psychological suffering.

ReferencesKearl (1983), Kelly (1991), Jackson (1995), Gillon (1998), Giesen (2012), Gur (2014).Lenke and Nemes (1985), Jackson (1995), Sullivan (2000), Pioro et al. (2008), Hassan et al. (2014), Hensel (2005).
Wrongful lifeWrongful birth
ActionClaim brought by or on behalf of a child.Claim brought by the parents.
ClaimsThe child has suffered from birth defects because the doctor is responsible for the undesired life.
  • The parents of a child born with birth defects, because of medical malpractice, were deprived of the opportunity to decide whether to terminate the pregnancy.

  • Self-determination of the mother was undermined.

  • There was a lack of information or understanding by mother/parents regarding the potential risks of having children with genetic or congenital anomalies, particularly in light of developments in prenatal diagnosis.

Damages
  • A life of pain and suffering of the child himself.

  • Costs for the maintenance of the disabled life.

  • Costs for the maintenance of the disabled child.

  • Impossibility of freely deciding their own family context.

  • Moral and psychological suffering.

ReferencesKearl (1983), Kelly (1991), Jackson (1995), Gillon (1998), Giesen (2012), Gur (2014).Lenke and Nemes (1985), Jackson (1995), Sullivan (2000), Pioro et al. (2008), Hassan et al. (2014), Hensel (2005).

The topic of wrongful birth bears witness to the increasing value of information in doctor–patient relationships. This is supported by the copious scholarly literature which has, over time, shaped the contents, methods, times and sequences of information that should be given to patients within this relationship (Turillazzi et al., 2014). A lack of information has thus become a legal question which affords ample scope for claims by patients unable to exercise their right to an informed acceptance (or indeed, refusal) of treatment (Akazaki, 1999).

The role of information may become particularly complex, as in this case, when the decision of the patient (the mother) affects others (the unborn or newborn child, father and siblings), including the physician whose conduct has conditioned such a decision. These are cases where a lack of, or wrong, information regarding the malformation or chromosomic anomalies of the foetus, has denied the pregnant mother the right to exercise the ‘faculty’ of interrupting the pregnancy, thus resulting in the birth of an ‘unhealthy’ child (Frati et al., 2014). For this reason, the professional relationship should be directed both towards checking for foetal malformations and (in the event of a positive result) exercising the right to interrupt the pregnancy.

The conceptual paradigm, therefore, builds on the fact that the woman has made it clear that she desires a ‘healthy child’ (at the risk of interrupting the pregnancy) and therefore, the doctor's role is to suggest (and explain) all the possibilities for ‘safely’ determining the conditions of the foetus (Dimopoulos and Bagaric, 2003). The doctor is obliged, in such cases, to provide complete information regarding (all) possible diagnostic tests, including their level of invasiveness and risk, as well as the percentage of false negatives offered by the test chosen. Further tests should be proposed (but certainly not carried out routinely) as a possible alternative, outlining the risks they carry, so as to allow the pregnant mother to decide what is best for her pregnancy.

Wrongful birth claims: looking for the international roadmap

Wrongful birth claims are brought by the parents of a child born with severe defects against a physician whose alleged negligence in the PD deprived the parents of the opportunity to take an informed decision about whether to avoid or terminate the pregnancy.

Over the years there have been different kinds of situations that have been indented in this type of litigation: cases in which, due to negligent conduct, a foetal anomaly that would have led the mother to have an abortion was not diagnosed (Virginia Supreme Court; Naccash v. Burger, 1982); cases where an abortion in a woman with special risks was not achieved (Pennsylvania Supreme Court; Speck v. Finegold, 1981); and cases of sterilization procedures not properly handled by negligence (Court for the District of Columbia; Hartke v. McKelway, 1981; Jha, 2016).

Historical references to the evolution of this particular kind of damage are required in order to better understand the meaning of this particular request for compensation and damages, as well as the difference with the damage from ‘wrongful life’ and why in most cases the requests from wrongful birth are accepted while those from wrongful life are rejected.

In the United States, in the 1970s, wrongful birth actions were meant to be those actions made by the couple when an unintended birth occurred; these claims were addressed to the manufacturers of contraceptive methods, and against doctors who had administered ineffective drugs or had not carried out a proper sterilization. As a matter of fact, in that period, the evolution of contraceptive techniques, such as sterilization and birth control pills, began to allow birth control on the part of couples, raising the need for a real ‘family planning’. The claims for compensation were primarily targeted to reparation for the medical expenses related to pregnancy and childbirth, the pain and suffering, as well as the costs for the growth and education of the child (Court for the Southern District of West Virginia; Whittington v. Eli Lilly, 1971).

With the development of non-therapeutic abortion laws and genetic diagnosis, an evolution of case law concerning the ‘wrongful birth’ has arisen on the basis of the growing importance of the woman self-determination principle, since she is the holder of the right to abortion in the presence of foetal malformations. The evolution of genetic diagnostics has allowed doctors to promptly recognize, even in early pregnancy, the presence of certain foetal malformations and has inevitably resulted in an increase in legal actions related to the use of such techniques, expanding the types of damage required. This obliged the doctors to offer the proper genetic testing, to correctly interpret the results and to inform parents promptly (DuBois, 2001; Carey, 2005). Therefore, due to these developments in science and jurisprudence, also the damage from ‘wrongful birth’ has evolved; as a matter of fact it is invoked by parents following the birth of an unwanted child because of his/her disability, in cases where the mother is deprived of the opportunity to decide whether to terminate the pregnancy (Moore, 1979).

The first wrongful birth claim presented at the Law Courts was in 1934, in the State of Minnesota, United States. In the specific case, Christensen v. Thornby, the Minnesota Supreme Court rejected the request of parents, decreeing that the birth of a new child was a blessed event.

A few decades later, an important jurisprudential current had been established. A first acknowledgement of wrongful birth damage was implemented by the Court of Texas in 1975, in the case Jacobs v. Theimer, 519 S.W.2d 846 (Tex. 1975). The case concerned a claim made by the parents of a child born with defects as a result of the contraction of rubella by the mother during the first month of pregnancy. Negligent conduct consisting of an incorrect diagnosis that had prevented the parent from terminating the pregnancy was contested to the clinicians. The Texas Supreme Court recognized, in this case, the damage caused by compensating the costs involved in the care and treatment of the child born with disabilities, but not the pain and emotional distress suffered by parents. In support of the acceptance of the compensation request, was the lack of information from physicians because the treatment or negligent advice had deprived the parents of the possibility to terminate the pregnancy.

The differences between the different types of damage that may be required as a result of wrongful birth and wrongful life were well established in 1996 by the Court of South Africa in the case of Friedman v. Glicksman: the wrongful birth damage regards the damages claimed by parents who would choose to terminate the pregnancy if properly informed of foetal defects/malformations, while the damage from wrongful life concerns the damages claimed by the child on the grounds that the lack of information about the malformation prevented parents from terminating the pregnancy, causing the birth of a child with disabilities, resulting in pain and suffering for the life of a ‘born malformed’ (Court of South Africa; Friedman v. Glicksman, 1996).

Nowadays, courts around the word generally allow wrongful birth actions.

In USA, the majority of States allow actions of wrongful birth: Alabama, Alaska, California, Colorado, Connecticut, Delaware, Florida, Illinois, Indiana, Iowa, Louisiana, Maryland, Massachusetts, Nevada, New Hampshire, New Jersey, New York, Rhode Island, Tennessee, Texas, Virginia, Washington, West Virginia, Wyoming (Maryland Court of Special Appeals, 2001). The words of the Supreme Court of New Hampshire sum up the case law of the American States that recognize the wrongful birth actions: ‘a wrongful birth claim is unlike any other medical malpractice action because it involves the uniquely personal choice to terminate a pregnancy or give birth to a child with the increased possibility of severe birth defects'. In this respect, a fact finder should also consider the plaintiff's emotional and physical ability to digest and act upon the information concerning the increased possibility of birth defects within the time period at issue, as well as her willingness and ability to travel to another jurisdiction to obtain an abortion during her third trimester, had she been able to arrange one (Supreme Court of New Hampshire; Hall v. Dartmouth Hitchcock Medical Center, 2006). In a more recent judgement of 2011, the Court of Illinois (Court of Illinois; Clark v. Children's Memorial Hospital, 2011) affirmed these principles and, furthermore, the compensable damage was recognized not only for the cost of the care of the disabled child (up to the 18th birthday) but also for the moral suffering (Hurley and McKenna, 2013). In a minority of states, however, the damage from wrongful birth is not recognized; in Liddington v. Burns (U.S. District Court for the Western District of Oklahoma, 1995), the Court of Oklahoma rejected the claim for two reasons: the first reason concerned the ultrasound test, as the result was not recognized as eligible to justify an abortion, and secondly, the Court rejected the request arguing that there was no indisputable evidence that the mother would have wanted and would have had an abortion in the first trimester of pregnancy. Furthermore, in some states, there is a specific article in the statues specifying that wrongful birth and/or wrongful life claims are banned: Kansas (K.S.A. 60-1906, 2013), South Dakota (SDCL 21-55-2, 1987), Oklahoma (63 Okl.St.Ann. 1-741.12, 2010), Missouri (V.A.M.S. 188.130, 1986), Michigan (M.C.L.A. 600.2971, 2011), Minnesota (M.S.A. 145.424, 2005), Maine (24 M.R.S.A. 2931,1990), Idaho (I.C. 5-334, 2010) and Arizona (A.R.S. 12-719, 2012) (Eagan, 2006; Pergament and Ilijic, 2014).

The Supreme Court of Canada, in Arndt v. Smith (2 S.C.R. 539, 1997) recognized ‘wrongful birth’ damage, justifying the decision with an interference with the right to choose an abortion. In this case, Carol Arndt sued her physician for not informing her of the risks associated with the contraction of chickenpox during pregnancy. During the dispute, the mother argued that, if properly informed about the risk of harm to the foetus, she would have terminated the pregnancy; on the other hand, the doctor contested that the patient would have still carried the pregnancy to term and that therefore he could not be attributed any responsibility (Rinaldi, 2009).

In the United Kingdom, in the 2000s, courts recognized substantial amounts including the expenses for the growth of a child born malformed, for loss of earnings and for the school. The leading case for such claims was the case of Parkinson v. St James e Seacroft Hospital NHS Trust (QB 266, 2002). On this occasion, the Court ordered the payment of damages caused by the birth of a disabled child due to a sterilization. A similar decision was adopted in the case of Rand v. East Dorset Health Authority (2000) Lloyd's Rep Med, in which the parents were not informed about the result of a test that showed that the mother was likely to give birth to a baby suffering from Down syndrome. The court held that the parents were entitled to claim compensation for damages related to the child support costs since they had not been able to exercise their right to terminate the pregnancy (Hassan et al., 2014). In 2002, in Rees v. Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust Ltd., the Court of Appeal ruled that the birth of a healthy but unplanned child brings additional costs; moreover, the judge stated that the mother has the right to claim compensation for damage caused by a birth due to a negligent conduct of the doctor (London Royal Courts of Justice; Rees v. Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust, 2003).

In Australia, the case law is very similar to that in the United Kingdom, as demonstrated by the case Cattanach v. Melchior, discussed by the High Court in 2003. In particular, most of the appeals have been received with recognition of the damage resulting from the loss of earnings and expenses for the maintenance of the child (Thomas, 2002). Moreover, in the case of Veivers v. Connolly 2 Qd R 326 on 1995, the Supreme Court of Queensland ruled in favour of a mother who had given birth to a child with severe disabilities due to negligent conduct of the doctor who failed to diagnose the mother with rubella and to inform her about the consequent risks for the foetus (Petersen, 1997).

In Ireland, the Constitutional right to life has a weighty impact on the effect of wrongful birth and life cases, as this right is extensively protected by the judiciary. In this regard, the most recent case law perceives the unborn child, whether healthy or disabled, as a blessing, resulting in rejection of the claims for compensation for damage caused by wrongful conception or wrongful birth cases (Alvarez, 2000). The fact that the child is a blessing and that he/she is very much wanted by the society in Ireland is evident within the provisions of the Constitution of Ireland 1937 as amended. In fact, the article 40.3.3 declares that ‘The State acknowledges the right to life of the unborn and, with due regard to the equal right to life of the mother, guarantees in its laws to respect, and, as far as practicable, by its laws to defend and vindicate that right.’ (Daly, 2005).

In the Netherlands, wrongful birth claims have been approved for many years; in 1997, with the particular so-called Missing IUD case, the Dutch Supreme Court (the Hoge Raad) recognized the compensation of the costs for the growth of the child as well as for non-economic damages in favour of the mother. Moreover, in a more recent judgement of 26 March 2003, the Court extensively clarified that this type of damage is to be recognized to parents. In this case, a foetal abnormality was not promptly recognized and the child was born with multiple malformations, both mental and physical. This negligence of the doctor resulted in violating the legal right of the mother to opt for an abortion. Therefore, damages against the hospital, amounting to the baby care costs, were also awarded to the parents (Nys and Dute, 2004).

In Germany, the German Supreme Court allowed wrongful birth claims in 1980 with two cases: the 76 BGHZ 249 and the 76 BGHZ 259; moreover, in the judgement of Bundesgerichtshof on 1983 the ‘wrongful birth’ claim was allowed because a disabled child was born as a consequence of a wrong diagnosis by the doctor; the compensation was recognized on the grounds of a negligent non-performance of contract (Dutch Federal Court of Justice, 1983; Carmi and Wax, 2002; Shaw, 1990). In recent years, the situation was rather difficult when it came to maintenance loss (non-pecuniary losses are awarded for the mother). This issue is still a matter of extensive debate; in fact, the German Federal Court of Justice is in favour of allowing a wrongful birth claim, awarding the costs of raising the child under certain conditions, but the Second Chamber of the constitutional court, the Federal Constitutional Court, is against this, considering these damages to be contrary to the dignity of the child. The Federal Court of Justice has remained true to its opinion, however, and these costs are generally compensated (van Gerven et al., 2001; Giesen, 2008).

The Austrian Supreme Court on 12 July 1990 (Juristische Blatter, 1991) applied the theory of informed consent and wrongful birth. In the decision at issue, the judges came to the conclusion that a physician does not need to inform about every single risk of medical therapy. With regard to wrongful birth, the court rejected the maintenance costs which were caused by a physician's negligent conduct because the doctor is not responsible for an unwanted pregnancy on the basis of informed consent (Bernat, 1992).

In Italy, the debate on the recognition of wrongful birth and wrongful life damages has been going for years. With the judgement no. 25767 on 22 December 2015, the Highest Italian Court provided a clear jurisprudence recognizing wrongful birth claims and rejecting wrongful life ones. The Court found that the inability of the woman to choose to terminate the pregnancy because of the negligence of the doctor, who had not properly informed her, is a source of civil liability; the request for damages made by the parents should, therefore, be accepted.

In Spain, wrongful birth claims are allowed but only if they are brought by the mother. The Supreme Court was clear on this matter, ruling that the right to opt for abortion constitutes a personal, non-transferable, right of the mother, which becomes an obstacle to a claim made exclusively by the father. The sentence of the Supreme Court of the 5 December 2007 had clarified the reasons stating that the abortion is a practice exclusively inherent to women. Concluding, solely the mother is entitled to claim compensation for wrongful birth damage, being the only holder of the right to abortion (Arantzazu Vicandi Martínez, 2013).

In Belgium, the Brussels Court of Appeal ruled that parents may sue physicians who fail to diagnose serious foetal malformations, assuming that parents, if properly informed, would proceed to the interruption of pregnancy. In particular, with the statement of the 21 September 2010, the Brussels Court of Appeal dealt with the case of a Muslim woman who complained that the hospital did not warn her of the serious illness affecting her foetus. The hospital justified the information defect arguing that the disease was found after the deadline prescribed by Islam for abortion. The Court, accepting the claim, concluded that the compensation must be accorded because the lack of information determined the birth of a child with disabilities (Court of Appeal of Brussels, 2010).

In France, the 4 March 2002 law stated that nobody can claim a damage resulting from the mere fact of being born, which leaves open a wide range of interpretations. In principle, a claim for child maintenance costs is deemed possible in cases of birth of a malformed child (in this occurrence, the non-pecuniary damage is also recognized) or in cases where the mother is in poor financial condition or develops mental problems after the baby is born. The birth of a healthy child is not considered a sufficient ground to justify the claim for damages (Viney and Jourdain, 2006).

In May 2011, the European Court of Human Rights ruled on wrongful birth. In the case R. R. v. Poland, a woman claimed that her access to prenatal genetic testing had been denied with the subsequent birth of a child suffering from Turner syndrome. The Court highlighted a violation regarding the prohibition of inhuman or degrading treatment and a violation of the right to respect for private and family life, thereby deciding in favour of the mother. In the judgement, it was also noted that the failure of the prenatal genetic test had violated the woman's right to health-related information and the right to personal autonomy.

In Japan, the claims for damages due to wrongful birth are generally accepted. The legal basis of this approach lies in the violation of the doctor's duty to give advice about the probability of the birth of a child with disabilities. In fact, the Japanese system does not provide foetal indications for abortion (Sakaihara, 2002).

In New Zealand, on the basis of the current legislation, there is no legal ability for either the parents or the child to obtain compensation for negligent prenatal genetic testing, even though the debate is still open. In this regard, the New Zealand Supreme Court recently ruled on the case Allenby v. H., considering that the law provides a coverage for pregnancies arising from medical misadventures (Tobin, 2005; Gordon, 2012; Cleary, 2013).

South African law recognizes claims for wrongful pregnancy and wrongful birth. The first case involving wrongful birth in a South African court was in 1996, in the matter of Friedman v. Glicksman; on that occasion, the mother of a child born with disabilities had accused the doctor because, if properly informed, she would have terminated the pregnancy. In its decision, the court upheld the appeal due to a breach of the contractual duty of the physician to properly inform the mother about the congenital deficits of her child (Strauss, 1996).

In Israel, actions for wrongful birth are allowed: in a recent sentence, on May 2012, Israeli Supreme Court declared that while wrongful birth claims were still permitted, wrongful life claims were no longer accepted in a court of law. Thus, the parents are entitled to compensation for the additional expenses required to fulfil their child's medical needs and support the child. In cases where the child continues to depend on the parents beyond childhood because of his/her disability, compensation is provided for the expenses resulting from the child's maintenance for the duration of his life (Mor, 2014).

In other countries, such as in Estonia, there is no a specific legislation and the debate is still open (Sõritsa and Lahe, 2014).

In the Czech Republic, the Brno Regional Court (judgement file No. 24 Co 66/2001) ordered an hospital to compensate the non-pecuniary damage suffered by a mother who had given birth to a healthy baby, despite her manifest desire to have an abortion. Emphasizing the right of the mother to decide about her unborn child, the High Court in Olomouc upheld the Regional Court decision in its decision on No. 1 Co 192/2008.

In Chile, a ‘wrongful birth’ claim is not admissible because in Chilean legislation abortions are always forbidden by law.

This review of the international case law shows that the majority of states recognize the wrongful birth claims.

In fact, in case of negligent conduct consisting on the breach of the doctor's duty to provide information about the presence of foetal malformations, the courts recognize the liability for violation of the right to self-determination of women, according to the principles of modern medical practice.

The foreclosure of the opportunity to make an informed choice about the interruption of pregnancy, resulting from the lack of information about the risk of giving birth to a child with disabilities, makes the physician responsible for damages resulting from an unwanted birth which is therefore deserving of a compensation claim.

Wrongful life

Claims of ‘wrongful life’ are made on behalf of the disabled child by his/her representatives, i.e. most notably the parents (Schmidt, 1983; Tucker, 1988–1989; Bottis, 2004). These claims, for having to live a life full of suffering because of a disability, are brought against a doctor or obstetrician. In these cases, the claim is that, overall, living is considered to bring more harm than good.

Although wrongful life is a highly debated topic (Liu, 1987; Sharman, 2001; Perry, 2007; DeGrazia, 2015; Francis, 2015), wrongful life claims have been brought against medical practitioners in many developed countries. Wrongful life cases are usually controversial and verdicts may differ between countries based on differences in the various legal jurisdictions (Giesen, 2012).

Wrongful life claims: an international overview

The term ‘wrongful life’ was first used in a case of illegitimate birth in the United States (Supreme Court of Illinois; Zepeda v. Zepeda, 1963).

The child claimed damages from his father for being an illegitimate child and suffering all the consequent hardships. The Illinois Supreme Court dismissed the case, focusing on the fact that the acceptance of a wrongful life claim would have legal and social implications and might encourage people to seek damages for any conditions they considered disadvantageous (Evgenia, 2012).

Nowadays, courts around the world are generally reluctant to acknowledge such claims due to their ethical and legal implications.

In the Netherlands, the Supreme Court recognized a wrongful life claim in the Kelly Molenaar case in March 2005. The Court granted living costs to a child born with a congenital malformation, i.e. for her upbringing, greater costs related to her disability and non-pecuniary losses for harmful individual experiences. Although it was affirmed that a life with a disability has no less value than a healthy life, it was acknowledged that the child's life would be more difficult (Nys and Dute, 2004; Sheldon, 2003, 2005). The Dutch legislators have not subsequently intervened on the matter, not even when asked specifically to consider doing so, affirming that the decision of the Supreme Court was in accordance with the rules of private law in the Netherlands and that there was no apparent reason for the legislator to decide otherwise on this issue (Giesen, 2012).

In Spain, wrongful life actions were first excluded and then indirectly allowed. The first time dates back to 1997 when the Supreme Court rejected a request, affirming that it was in clear contrast with the right to life and human dignity. Later, on 4 February 1998, 6 July 2007 and 4 November 2008, the Supreme Court confirmed its prior judgement, affirming that the birth of a diseased person is not an evil and that the birth of a child cannot be considered a damage. More recently, on 16 June 2010 and even prior to this, on 18 December 2003, the Supreme Court indirectly allowed wrongful life actions. Although it was denied that the birth of a child could be considered a damage, a baby born with a disability was awarded a lifelong monthly pension, inspired by social welfare principles (de Angel Yágüez, 2005).

In Germany, wrongful life actions are denied. The principal case concerns a child whose mother contracted rubella during pregnancy (BGH Bundesgerichtshof, 18 January 1983). The mother had not been informed about the risks of giving birth to a disabled child and, as legal guardian, she brought wrongful birth and wrongful life proceedings to ask for compensation on the child's behalf. The German judges recognized the validity of the mother's action while rejecting the wrongful life case, on the grounds that doctors do not have the obligation to impede the birth of a baby with congenital malformations, as to do so would be to undermine the value of human life itself (Giesen, 1988; Markesinis and Unberath, 2002).

Austria excludes wrongful life actions. The principal case is the Supreme Court's decision on 25 May 1999. According to the judge, the obligation of abortion in the event of a diagnosis of malformation does not exist in the Austrian judicial system; therefore, there was no causal relationship between the omitted diagnosis and the birth. The Austrian judges have considered unquantifiable the wrongful life damage and inadmissible the possibility for the child born with disabilities to bring proceedings even against his or her parents (Bernat, 1992).

In the United Kingdom, wrongful life claims are not recognized. Although the 1976 Congenital Disabilities Act allows the child to sue the doctor whose conduct was responsible for his or her disability, this possibility does not exist in the case of omitted information. In the famous 1982 McKay v. Essex Area Health Authority case, the legitimacy of wrongful life actions was categorically excluded (Queen's Bench, 1982). This is a landmark case for other common law courts. An erroneous diagnosis had led to the birth of a baby suffering from a severe disability, because of rubella contracted during the gestation period. The judges rejected the parents’ claim. There was conflict with the principle of the sanctity of human life, according to which all human life is of value and it is therefore inconceivable that the life of a disabled person is considered of lesser value than a healthy one. For the English judges, it was important to prevent the further risk of children born with disabilities bringing proceedings even against their own parents and pushing doctors towards defensive medicine, such as suggesting abortion in the case of foetal malformation diagnosis. In general, for the doctor, the duty of abortion does not exist; therefore there is no causal relationship between omission and birth. Such disability is congenital and cannot be attributed in any way to medical conduct (Jackson, 1996; Gur, 2014).

In France, wrongful life actions are not allowed but the debate on the topic became very interesting around 2000. In 1994, magistrates faced this issue for the first time with the Quarez case. The judges denied compensation to a child born with a disability because the maintenance costs were absorbed by the proceeding brought by his parents. The principal French case is the Perruche case (Cour de Cassation de France, 2000), in which a boy was born with a severe disability because of rubella contracted during pregnancy. In this case, the Supreme Court admitted the wrongful life action, recognizing the causal connection between the doctor's omission and the undesired birth (Dorozynski, 2001). This sentence provoked strong reaction from the public who judged that the decision infringed the right to life and human dignity. Despite this, a few months later, the Supreme Court pronounced up to five judgements between 13 July and 28 November 2001. Law no. 303 of 4 March 2002 embraced public opinion and excluded wrongful life actions, unless the disability was caused by medical conduct. The political choice was clear, i.e. to avoid qualifying life as compensable and passing on this charge to the medical profession. The French case is even more interesting because the legislator deemed the law to be retroactive, thus provoking the intervention of the European Court of Human Rights. Although the European Court recognized the legitimacy of the content of the legislation, it condemned the fact that it was retroactive (Loi Kouchner 2002; ECHR, Vo v. France, 2004; Clement and Rodat, 2006; Manaouil et al., 2012; Manaouil and Jardè, 2012).

A bill similar to the French one was proposed in Belgium in January 2002 but never became law. The court of first instance of Brussels has twice allowed a wrongful life claim under Belgian general tort law, citing the French Perruche case, and the Brussels’ Court of Appeal has recently (Court of Appeal of Brussels, 2010) also allowed a claim. The defendant has lodged an appeal at the Belgian Supreme Court. Currently in Belgium, wrongful life is still neither regulated nor clear (Giesen, 2012; Devisch, 2013).

In Italy, the position of judges in this regard were not entirely clear until a recent judgement of the Highest Court that seems to have finally closed the issue. Some judges used to recognize the right to compensation only for parents, while, recently, other judges have extended this right also to the child with congenital malformations. These disagreements led the Highest Italian Court to convene in a unifying resolution and to pronounce a judgement (no. 25767/22 December 2015) to be followed by all others Italian courts. Therefore, the right to compensation for wrongful life claims has definitely been excluded.

Also in Hungary, after an earlier acceptance of wrongful life claims, the Supreme Court (Unificatory Decision of no. 1/2008, 12 March 2008) established that wrongful life claims cannot be accepted under Hungarian law (Winiger et al., 2011). Greece, Poland and Portugal are also rejecting this kind of claim (Giesen, 2012). There is no case law for wrongful conception, wrongful birth and wrongful life in Estonia (Sõritsa and Lahe, 2014).

The state of Israel recognized wrongful life actions for more than twenty years. This changed in 2012 with the Hammer decision, interrupting a jurisprudential line that went as far back as 1986 with the Zeitsov v. Katz case (Levi, 1987; Carmi, 1990). For the judges, the acknowledgement of the right to compensation aimed to improve the quality of a life that had begun with an inferior condition and was characterized by pain, since there were few socio-economic structures to help and assist disabled people. In May 2012, with the Hammer v. Amit case, the Israeli Supreme Court banned these actions, thereby refusing recognition of the right not to be born if not in good health (Israeli Supreme Court, 2012; Mor, 2014).

Canadian (Toews and Caulfield, 2014) and most American courts also deny this cause of action. The American States that allow wrongful life actions are the State of California with the Curlender v. Bioscience Laboratories case and the Turpin v. Sortini case, the State of Washington with the Haberson v. Parke-Davis case and the State of New Jersey with the Prokanic v. Cillo case (VanDerhoef, 1983). The Californian case is perhaps the most interesting one because it overturns a previous line that had excluded the legitimacy of such actions. The judges of Curlender v. Bioscience Laboratories case, rejecting the explanatory statements regarding the sanctity of life and the impossibility of measuring the difference between a life with deficiencies and the emptiness of non-existing adopted up to that moment, allowed wrongful life actions and the fact that a disabled person's life could be compensable. After 2 years, in 1982, with the Turpin v. Sortini case, the Californian judges allowed such actions, specifying, however, that they could be made only against doctors and not against parents, as this would restrict the latter's freedom of choice in the procreative domain. However, in contrast to the Curlender v. Bioscience Laboratories case, the judges restricted the compensation just to the major costs connected to disability. The other states are essentially in agreement with the Californian judges’ position (Laufer, 1982; Steinbock, 1986; Klein and Mahoney, 2007).

Although in Japan a child who is born disabled is able to file a claim against the person who injured him or her in the mother's womb (Sakaihara, 2007) and cases of wrongful birth claims have been awarded (Sakaihara, 2002), to the best of our knowledge no wrongful life lawsuits against medical practitioners have been filed in Japan.

In Australia, claims regarding both wrongful life and wrongful birth cases have been brought to the attention of the courts. In 2003 a High Court decision stated that damages may not only be awarded for pain and suffering and any loss of income due to the pregnancy and birth, but also for the costs of raising the child to 18 years of age. Following this decision, legislation was introduced in New South Wales, Queensland and South Australia preventing an award of damages for the costs of raising a child in ‘wrongful birth’ claims. In 2006 a decision of the High Court (High Court of Australia, 2006; New South Wales Court of Appeal, 2015) regarding a wrongful life claim established that disabled children are unable to sue medical practitioners for wrongful life, but the parents of disabled children are still able to pursue a claim in their own right for wrongful birth in the case of medical negligence (Devereux, 2002; Connors, 2005; Bird, 2006; Faunce and Jefferys, 2007).

Along the same lines are judgments of claims in Korea (Um, 2000) and in Singapore (Giesen, 2012).

Finally, the South African Supreme Court of Appeal, while assessing that healthcare practitioners who failed to detect and inform parents of congenital anomalies in the foetus so that they could have considered termination of pregnancy were liable to pay damages for wrongful birth, denied the wrongful life claim from the same child (South Africa Supreme Court of Appeal, 2008). The Court held that the law cannot adjudicate on the questions of existentialism, ‘which would require a court to determine whether a child should have been born, since this goes to the heart of what it is to be human’ (Chima and Mamdoo, 2015).

In conclusion, a glance at the international scenarios highlights the fact that the courts have overwhelmingly rejected wrongful life actions while at the same time approving those for wrongful birth (Tables II and III).

Table II

International state of law: wrongful Life allowed or not clear.

StatesCasesSolutions
NetherlandKelly Molenaar, 2005
  • Child would live a life with greater difficulties.

  • Costs of maintenance of the disabled life.

USA:
 (1) State of California (1) Curlender v. Bio Lab; Turpin v. SortiniA disabled person's life could be compensable.
 (2) State of Washington (2) Heberson v. Parke-DavisIn Turpin case, compensation was just for the major costs connected to disability.
 (3) State of New Jersey (3) Prokanic v. Cillo
BelgiumCour d'Appel Bruxelles, 21 Sept 2010, but the case is still in progress → The position of Belgium is actually not clear.There is a causal relationship between the doctor's omissive practice and the undesired birth.
SpainTribunal Supremo, Jun 2010, rec. 448/2008Child would live a life with disability due to unwanted birth. The tools to limit the pain, suffering and distress were provided by a requirement to pay a monthly pension for life. → Wronguful Life action indirectly allowed.
JapanNo cases foundThe position of Japan is not clear but a child who is born disabled is able to file a claim against the person who injured him or her in the mother's womb; cases of wrongful birth claims have been awarded.
StatesCasesSolutions
NetherlandKelly Molenaar, 2005
  • Child would live a life with greater difficulties.

  • Costs of maintenance of the disabled life.

USA:
 (1) State of California (1) Curlender v. Bio Lab; Turpin v. SortiniA disabled person's life could be compensable.
 (2) State of Washington (2) Heberson v. Parke-DavisIn Turpin case, compensation was just for the major costs connected to disability.
 (3) State of New Jersey (3) Prokanic v. Cillo
BelgiumCour d'Appel Bruxelles, 21 Sept 2010, but the case is still in progress → The position of Belgium is actually not clear.There is a causal relationship between the doctor's omissive practice and the undesired birth.
SpainTribunal Supremo, Jun 2010, rec. 448/2008Child would live a life with disability due to unwanted birth. The tools to limit the pain, suffering and distress were provided by a requirement to pay a monthly pension for life. → Wronguful Life action indirectly allowed.
JapanNo cases foundThe position of Japan is not clear but a child who is born disabled is able to file a claim against the person who injured him or her in the mother's womb; cases of wrongful birth claims have been awarded.
Table II

International state of law: wrongful Life allowed or not clear.

StatesCasesSolutions
NetherlandKelly Molenaar, 2005
  • Child would live a life with greater difficulties.

  • Costs of maintenance of the disabled life.

USA:
 (1) State of California (1) Curlender v. Bio Lab; Turpin v. SortiniA disabled person's life could be compensable.
 (2) State of Washington (2) Heberson v. Parke-DavisIn Turpin case, compensation was just for the major costs connected to disability.
 (3) State of New Jersey (3) Prokanic v. Cillo
BelgiumCour d'Appel Bruxelles, 21 Sept 2010, but the case is still in progress → The position of Belgium is actually not clear.There is a causal relationship between the doctor's omissive practice and the undesired birth.
SpainTribunal Supremo, Jun 2010, rec. 448/2008Child would live a life with disability due to unwanted birth. The tools to limit the pain, suffering and distress were provided by a requirement to pay a monthly pension for life. → Wronguful Life action indirectly allowed.
JapanNo cases foundThe position of Japan is not clear but a child who is born disabled is able to file a claim against the person who injured him or her in the mother's womb; cases of wrongful birth claims have been awarded.
StatesCasesSolutions
NetherlandKelly Molenaar, 2005
  • Child would live a life with greater difficulties.

  • Costs of maintenance of the disabled life.

USA:
 (1) State of California (1) Curlender v. Bio Lab; Turpin v. SortiniA disabled person's life could be compensable.
 (2) State of Washington (2) Heberson v. Parke-DavisIn Turpin case, compensation was just for the major costs connected to disability.
 (3) State of New Jersey (3) Prokanic v. Cillo
BelgiumCour d'Appel Bruxelles, 21 Sept 2010, but the case is still in progress → The position of Belgium is actually not clear.There is a causal relationship between the doctor's omissive practice and the undesired birth.
SpainTribunal Supremo, Jun 2010, rec. 448/2008Child would live a life with disability due to unwanted birth. The tools to limit the pain, suffering and distress were provided by a requirement to pay a monthly pension for life. → Wronguful Life action indirectly allowed.
JapanNo cases foundThe position of Japan is not clear but a child who is born disabled is able to file a claim against the person who injured him or her in the mother's womb; cases of wrongful birth claims have been awarded.
Table III

International state of law: wrongful life denied

StatesCasesSolutions
ItalyItalian Supreme Court, Joined Chambers, no. 25767 of 22 December 2015
  • It is not possible that the doctor, responsible for not giving the mother a full information, has to compensate also the child.

  • The disabled child's life cannot be considered a damage, assuming it has less value than the life of a healthy child.

  • There is no damage.

FranceLaw no. 303 of 4 March 2002
  • Wrongful Life actions are definitely excluded unless it has been the medical conduct itself causing the malformation.

  • Human life is not a compensable damage.

  • It is not possible to ascribe to the society the maintenance costs of children born with disabilities.

GermanyBGH 18 Jan 1983The doctors do not have the obligation to prevent the birth of a malformed child.
AustriaOGH 25 May 1999Absence of causal relationship between the omiited diagnosis and the birth.
HungarySupreme Court, Unificatory Resolution,
no. 1/2008
  • The rights protected by Law (e.g. life, human dignity, economic interests) are not infringed by the fact of being born.

  • Life could not constitute damage.

United KingdomMcKay v. Essex Area Health Authority, 1982
  • Human life has value in any case: principle of the sanctity of human life.

  • A disabled person's life is not considered of a lesser value than a healthy person's life.

AustraliaHarriton v. Stephen and Waller v. Jans, 2006
  • It is impossibile to calculate damages.

  • A disabled person's life should not be devalued.

  • There is an absence of causal relationship between medical pracitise and birth of a disabled child.

South AfricaFriedman v. Glicksman, 1996 and Stewart v.Botha, 2007The law cannot adjudicate on the questions of existentialism.
IsraelHamer v. Amit, May 2012
  • The right ‘not to be born’ if not in good health is not recognized.

  • Wrongful life claims send a negative message about a life with a disability.

CanadaBovington v. Hergott, 2008
  • A child cannot claim to have suffered harm as a result of their birth.

  • It is better to be alive than never been born.

StatesCasesSolutions
ItalyItalian Supreme Court, Joined Chambers, no. 25767 of 22 December 2015
  • It is not possible that the doctor, responsible for not giving the mother a full information, has to compensate also the child.

  • The disabled child's life cannot be considered a damage, assuming it has less value than the life of a healthy child.

  • There is no damage.

FranceLaw no. 303 of 4 March 2002
  • Wrongful Life actions are definitely excluded unless it has been the medical conduct itself causing the malformation.

  • Human life is not a compensable damage.

  • It is not possible to ascribe to the society the maintenance costs of children born with disabilities.

GermanyBGH 18 Jan 1983The doctors do not have the obligation to prevent the birth of a malformed child.
AustriaOGH 25 May 1999Absence of causal relationship between the omiited diagnosis and the birth.
HungarySupreme Court, Unificatory Resolution,
no. 1/2008
  • The rights protected by Law (e.g. life, human dignity, economic interests) are not infringed by the fact of being born.

  • Life could not constitute damage.

United KingdomMcKay v. Essex Area Health Authority, 1982
  • Human life has value in any case: principle of the sanctity of human life.

  • A disabled person's life is not considered of a lesser value than a healthy person's life.

AustraliaHarriton v. Stephen and Waller v. Jans, 2006
  • It is impossibile to calculate damages.

  • A disabled person's life should not be devalued.

  • There is an absence of causal relationship between medical pracitise and birth of a disabled child.

South AfricaFriedman v. Glicksman, 1996 and Stewart v.Botha, 2007The law cannot adjudicate on the questions of existentialism.
IsraelHamer v. Amit, May 2012
  • The right ‘not to be born’ if not in good health is not recognized.

  • Wrongful life claims send a negative message about a life with a disability.

CanadaBovington v. Hergott, 2008
  • A child cannot claim to have suffered harm as a result of their birth.

  • It is better to be alive than never been born.

Table III

International state of law: wrongful life denied

StatesCasesSolutions
ItalyItalian Supreme Court, Joined Chambers, no. 25767 of 22 December 2015
  • It is not possible that the doctor, responsible for not giving the mother a full information, has to compensate also the child.

  • The disabled child's life cannot be considered a damage, assuming it has less value than the life of a healthy child.

  • There is no damage.

FranceLaw no. 303 of 4 March 2002
  • Wrongful Life actions are definitely excluded unless it has been the medical conduct itself causing the malformation.

  • Human life is not a compensable damage.

  • It is not possible to ascribe to the society the maintenance costs of children born with disabilities.

GermanyBGH 18 Jan 1983The doctors do not have the obligation to prevent the birth of a malformed child.
AustriaOGH 25 May 1999Absence of causal relationship between the omiited diagnosis and the birth.
HungarySupreme Court, Unificatory Resolution,
no. 1/2008
  • The rights protected by Law (e.g. life, human dignity, economic interests) are not infringed by the fact of being born.

  • Life could not constitute damage.

United KingdomMcKay v. Essex Area Health Authority, 1982
  • Human life has value in any case: principle of the sanctity of human life.

  • A disabled person's life is not considered of a lesser value than a healthy person's life.

AustraliaHarriton v. Stephen and Waller v. Jans, 2006
  • It is impossibile to calculate damages.

  • A disabled person's life should not be devalued.

  • There is an absence of causal relationship between medical pracitise and birth of a disabled child.

South AfricaFriedman v. Glicksman, 1996 and Stewart v.Botha, 2007The law cannot adjudicate on the questions of existentialism.
IsraelHamer v. Amit, May 2012
  • The right ‘not to be born’ if not in good health is not recognized.

  • Wrongful life claims send a negative message about a life with a disability.

CanadaBovington v. Hergott, 2008
  • A child cannot claim to have suffered harm as a result of their birth.

  • It is better to be alive than never been born.

StatesCasesSolutions
ItalyItalian Supreme Court, Joined Chambers, no. 25767 of 22 December 2015
  • It is not possible that the doctor, responsible for not giving the mother a full information, has to compensate also the child.

  • The disabled child's life cannot be considered a damage, assuming it has less value than the life of a healthy child.

  • There is no damage.

FranceLaw no. 303 of 4 March 2002
  • Wrongful Life actions are definitely excluded unless it has been the medical conduct itself causing the malformation.

  • Human life is not a compensable damage.

  • It is not possible to ascribe to the society the maintenance costs of children born with disabilities.

GermanyBGH 18 Jan 1983The doctors do not have the obligation to prevent the birth of a malformed child.
AustriaOGH 25 May 1999Absence of causal relationship between the omiited diagnosis and the birth.
HungarySupreme Court, Unificatory Resolution,
no. 1/2008
  • The rights protected by Law (e.g. life, human dignity, economic interests) are not infringed by the fact of being born.

  • Life could not constitute damage.

United KingdomMcKay v. Essex Area Health Authority, 1982
  • Human life has value in any case: principle of the sanctity of human life.

  • A disabled person's life is not considered of a lesser value than a healthy person's life.

AustraliaHarriton v. Stephen and Waller v. Jans, 2006
  • It is impossibile to calculate damages.

  • A disabled person's life should not be devalued.

  • There is an absence of causal relationship between medical pracitise and birth of a disabled child.

South AfricaFriedman v. Glicksman, 1996 and Stewart v.Botha, 2007The law cannot adjudicate on the questions of existentialism.
IsraelHamer v. Amit, May 2012
  • The right ‘not to be born’ if not in good health is not recognized.

  • Wrongful life claims send a negative message about a life with a disability.

CanadaBovington v. Hergott, 2008
  • A child cannot claim to have suffered harm as a result of their birth.

  • It is better to be alive than never been born.

Critical issues arising from wrongful life claims

Analysis of the different jurisdictional solutions shows that wrongful life claims are generally rejected for several reasons. These include ethical and social concerns in admitting that non-existence is better than being born with a disability, and the difficulty in calculating damages for having been born with a disability as opposed to not having been born at all (Jones and Perry, 1983; Young, 2004; Kapteiran, 2006).

Wrongful life and wrongful birth issues lie at the intersection of law and ethics. From an ethical point of view, wrongful life claims seem to involve weighing the value of non-existence against life with a disability. Wrongful life is controversial because it appears to identify the impaired child's life as an injury, a concept contrary to many deeply held beliefs in society. The traditional reason given when rejecting wrongful life actions is the fact that life is never an injury. The courts generally refuse to recognize this kind of claim because of the presumption that life in any condition is preferable to non-existence, and therefore can never be an injury; as a matter of fact, the majority of countries have rejected wrongful life actions while at the same time approving those for wrongful birth (Fig. 1).
Figure 1

Overview of the countries that accept or reject wrongful life actions.

Because alleged medical negligence does not actually cause the child's impairment, but instead enables the child to come into being, the operable injury is the child's life itself, with non-existence identified as the preferred alternative.

Thus, the life-as-injury seems to be the Gordian knot of the robust ethical debate surrounding the issue of wrongful life claims, which is characterized by strong emotive labelling. There are ‘situations in which the burdens of life outweigh its benefits, thereby enabling life to be termed ‘wrongful’ in life’ (Jackson, 1996). Damage to the child should, then, be measured not as part of the life versus non-life dilemma, nor regarding a hypothesized ‘non-value of a disabled life’ but, rather, in terms of the functional level of infirmity and the developmental possibilities of a life with disabilities. What it amounts to is not simply an algebraic sum of life plus disability but, in essence, a disabled life.

There should be no distinction, therefore, between the sacredness of life and quality of life. Instead, regardless of subjective perceptions of quality of life, emphasis should be placed on health, understood as being ‘not only within the static dimensions of absence of illness but as a dynamic/functional condition of mental-physical wellbeing’.

The ‘tragedy’ of a particularly severe disability which is a constitutive part of the child's biography and will be so for life, yet which does not diminish the child's dignity as a human being, justifies taking the greatest care both of the child and of all the other subjects (family members) involved.

The philosophical literature is rich in strong emotional references: ‘empty of all the things that make life worth living’ (Steinbock, 2009), ‘dominated by pain and suffering’ (Bennett, 2009), ‘intractably miserable’ (Rakowski, 2002), ‘not worth living’ (Feinberg, 1986) or ‘worse than no life at all’ (Brock, 1995). Contrasting views on this issue address the core of the question in different ways: whether children have the right to pursue damages for having been born and to claim that they would have been better off aborted or not conceived.

Those who reject wrongful life suits claim that one cannot be harmed by being conceived, born or being brought to life (Kennedy, 1983; Feinberg, 1984; Parfit, 1984; Roberts, 2003), mostly basing their arguments on the fact that if one was not conceived, then one would never have existed at all (Parfit, 1984). In this respect Feinberg's words are illuminating: "To be harmed is to be put in a worse condition than one would otherwise be in (to be made ‘worse off’), but if the negligent act had not occurred, B would not have existed at all. The creation of an initial condition is not the worsening of a prior condition; therefore, it is not an act of harming, no matter how harmful it is” (Feinberg, 1984). Moreover, those who disallow the feasibility of wrongful life suits fear that the endorsement of the above claim is tantamount to an affirmation that non-life is preferable to a life afflicted with disease and that a perilous ‘slippery slope’ could be triggered by wrongful life claims. Shapira, while supporting the thesis that it would be both feasible and desirable to endorse wrongful life compensation actions, says: "And what if a child seeks compensation for ‘wrongful life’ not from a genetic counsellor but from his or her parents, claiming that were it not for their parental imprudence, he or she would not have been born into a life burdened by any number of disadvantages—genetic illness or HIV infection, the stigma of illegitimacy, religious persecution or ethnic prejudice, racial discrimination or socio-economic deprivation?” (Shapira, 1998).

Finally, it has also been argued that torts like wrongful life may reinforce a negative image of disability in society, since juries in such actions are required to evaluate whether a disability is so terrible as to make plausible the mother's decision to abort, or the non-existence of the disabled child. The centrality of impairment in defining personhood could be reinforced by wrongful life torts, thus strengthening discriminatory beliefs regarding disabled persons (Hensel, 2005). In other words, at the individual level, the beneficial effects of recognizing a monetary compensation in wrongful life claims are clearly undeniable. However, the use of the judiciary tool (via wrongful life actions) to obtain the necessary assistance seems to some legal scholars to reflect ‘the benevolent paternalism embedded in the medical model of disability, in which the nondisabled ‘assume the role of protectors, guides and spokespersons for disabled citizens’ without ever challenging the ‘attitudinal discrimination’ in society’ (Harlan, 1994; Hensel, 2005).

On the other hand, supporters of the legitimacy of wrongful life claims argue against the supposed illogicalness and incoherence of these actions, focusing on the fact that it is not a necessary and a sufficient condition that one is worse off than his/her prior condition in order to assign harm to his/her current condition (Muriithi, 2011), and that a comparison has to be made between the actual impaired life of a plaintiff and the hypothetical unimpaired life rather than between defective life and non-existence (Shapira, 1998; Dimopoulos and Bagaric, 2003; Morris and Saintier, 2003).

In the final analysis, contrasting views on the issue of wrongful life claims are difficult to reconcile; on one hand there are those who view wrongful life actions as a threat with a very disturbing message, i.e. non-existence is never preferable to life, however, burdened. On the other hand, the conceptual position favourable to wrongful life claims is based on the assertion that being conceived, born or being brought to existence can be harmful, without entering into an emotional comparison between existence and non-existence.

The decision that a particular life is not worth living is a very difficult one as the notion that life, however, impaired, is always preferable to non-existence would be challenged as unsound. Some American Courts have expressed the concept that human experience does not make possible the life–non-existence comparison necessitated by the wrongful life action (Supreme Court of New Jersey, Berman v. Allan, 1979; Supreme Court of California, Turpin v. Sortini, 1982). On these grounds, one of the main criticisms of wrongful life action takes on a ‘grass is always greener’ approach. The child has never experienced a healthy life, and, when born, will have life experiences relative to her disability. Accordingly, the child suffers nothing since all that she/he knows is her/his actual condition with its concomitant pain and suffering (Belsky, 1993). Thus the phrase ‘wrongful life’ seems to be counterintuitive since a comparison between a situation where an individual exists and a situation in where that individual does not exist, made for the purpose of establishing whether the individual is better or worse off in either situation is thought to be impossible (Stretton, 2006). However, it may be argued that it is not entirely impossible to compare existence with non-existence. Echoing Stretton (Stretton, 2006), ‘one cannot, for example, imagine what it is like to be unconscious: there is nothing unconsciousness is like, no (conscious) experience to be imagined. Yet one can compare unconsciousness with consciousness and say, for example, that it is better to be awake and having pleasant, conscious experiences, than to be comatosed. Indeed, that very comparison leads to the award of damages for loss of enjoyment of life’. Furthermore, it may be argued that sometimes non-existence is preferable to certain kinds of life (Stretton, 2005, 2006). To express this more clearly, ‘normally’ a great part of us are glad to exist and think that life is better than non-existence. This is not because non-existence is bad, but because non-existence is nothingness, and therefore has zero value, whereas life is for the most part good, and therefore has greater than zero value (Nagel, 1986). As a consequence, most of us would prefer to continue living than to die or be killed. However, the ethical reflection on the issue leads to a subsequent question: how bad would life have to be to be worse than non-existence? Are there some disabilities so severe that they make life not worth living? Does a minimally bearable quality of life exist? Examples drawn from jurisprudential US cases may help us to understand. In Harriton (2006) 226 ALR 391, 415, Kirby J tried to explain ‘Consider the situation of a newborn child who has a very limited life span and has no capacity to think or appreciate his or her surroundings and is only capable of experiencing unrelenting and excruciating pain. In such a case, many people might think that non-existence would be preferable to existence, particularly where heroic measures were necessary to keep the patient alive.’ Even common sense and medical experience may help us in this conceptual framework. For irretrievably damaged human beings who have lost all higher cerebral functions, curled up on a hospital bed with tubes and wires sustaining and monitoring their vital functions, for people who suffer from constant pain, from limitation of movement and sensation, from severe impairment of the ability to interact with other people, life might be worse than death (Savulescu, 2002). It may, however, be hard to affirm that in mild to moderate intellectual disability non-existence is better to life since a children with intellectual disability may live a happy and worthwhile existence (Savulescu, 2002). On the other hand, some people think that even Down's syndrome constitutes a life not worth living (Molenaar, 1992). When we are dealing with ethical concerns of wrongful life claims, we must consider that evaluation of quality of life. Whether life is worth living is difficult to assess on objective grounds. Even if we acquiesce in the view that the absence of pain and suffering, e.g. could be assumed as objective criteria to evaluate the quality of life, as to when the threshold is crossed with respect to whether life is or is not worth living, remains a difficult, almost impossible question.

Wrongful life claims and medical liability

Beyond the rich bioethical and philosophical debate on the metaphysical question related to the comparison between existence and non-existence, the practical reality of an injured child exists. The child will experience pain and suffering during his/her lifetime and, depending on his/her incapacity and dependence, will have to bear pecuniary damages and losses for the high cost of medical and social care that often accompanies severe impairments. Despite the general reluctance of the courts all over the world to allow wrongful life claims, many scholars and commentators have offered these arguments in support of these torts, sustaining that wrongful birth and wrongful life correspond closely, if not perfectly, to traditional negligence principles and should be analysed under traditional negligence framework and tort principles (Kelly, 1991; Belsky, 1993; Jackson, 1995; Caulfield, 2001).

As part of tort doctrine has outlined ‘the terms wrongful birth and wrongful life are confusing because they seem to indicate a unique or novel claim for relief, when they are merely tort claims sounding in traditional negligence or medical malpractice. Wrongful birth is a misnomer that does not identify the underlying tort as much as it unartfully describes the result of tort. The same conclusion is true for wrongful life’ (Jankowski, 1989).

Consequently, in the midst of the robust debate surrounding wrongful life claims, possible ramifications in the medical liability nightmare deserve our close attention. The emergent technologies in the field of PD raise expectations in parents that cannot always be met, and unwittingly open the door to less straightforward challenges for medical practitioners (Pattinson, 1999). All the issues surrounding wrongful life claims raise a critical question: the physician does not cause the disease or the defect in the child; rather it is the physician's failure to advise the mother/parents adequately, thereby depriving them of the chance to make a fully informed decision, which is the central core of the claims (Howlett et al., 2002).

In many wrongful life cases, the pertinent claim is that there has been a problem with information or understanding by mother/parents regarding the potential risks of having children with genetic or congenital anomalies, the results of the tests performed, and finally the accuracy of the tests themselves. Improvements in information and consent practice are undoubtedly to be sought, particularly in the light of developments of PD, and practitioners will need to maintain high standards of counselling to facilitate informed consent (Rafi and Chitty, 2009), and offer the most appropriate prenatal test. In other words, the Gordian knot is the physician's ability to guide pregnant women towards a full understanding of the prenatal tests on offer. Information and consent are not merely ethical challenges in prenatal screening and diagnosis (de Jong et al., 2015), but key points in avoiding malpractice claims (Localio et al., 1991; Beckman et al., 1994; Hickson et al., 1994; Levinson et al., 1997; Brenner and Bartholomew, 2005; de Reuver et al., 2008; Ricci et al., 2015). Key points arise for physicians who are obliged to counsel and offer screening for relatively common genetic diseases and for a standard body of infectious disease, to offer evaluation for particular risks related to race or age, and for specific risks related to personal, familial and medical history, and finally to correctly interpret and communicate the results of the tests performed (Klein and Mahoney, 2007).

As a consequence, a breach of duty occurs when the physicians fails to utilize the most adequate prenatal diagnostic procedures, to consider the family or personal history of the mother, to inquire into the parents’ ethnicity or, finally, to interpret or communicate the information. And this breach of duty may wrongfully cause suffering in the life of the child.

Conclusions

There are many conceptual difficulties relating to bioethics and the law.

Conclusively, wrongful life suits are alleged to be predicated on the devaluation of life with disability, i.e. that non-existence is preferable to life with disability. The injury is therefore life with disability. Wrongful life claims seek to compensate the child (the victim) by comparing his/her rightful condition had the defendant not acted negligently, with her actual conditions of life. As we have seen above, this comparison (where the alternative would be non-existence, the termination of a pregnancy) draws the most bioethical and juridical criticisms and is largely responsible for the fact that many courts, internationally, deny the feasibility and the lawfulness of wrongful life suits. The claim that non-existence is preferable to life with disability stands as the major obstacle and is the main justification for the dismissal of many cases of wrongful life claims.

In wrongful birth claims, parents of the child bring their own claim since they allege that a deed of medical negligence has led to the birth of an unwanted, often disabled child. The child's life is injurious to them, since they are obliged to live with upbringing costs and the duty of nursing a child who will not live a healthy life. However, unlike wrongful life action, an action for wrongful birth seems not to imply a conceptual parallel between the child's life with a ‘handicap’ and non-existence. In wrongful birth claims, parents seek lost earnings, child rearing expenses, emotional distress damages and reimbursement for the extraordinary expenses occasioned by the child's disability. Moreover, the injury of wrongful birth claims is sometimes referred to in the literature as the deprivation of choice (Rinaldi, 2009), since parents allege that they were unable to make fully informed choices due to a lack of medical information. On this issue, according to Hensel, it could be argued that wrongful life suits tend to be less successful than wrongful birth claims because ‘in part … courts have found it more palatable to identify lost parental choice as the injury than to answer the metaphysical question of whether non-existence is ever preferable to life, however burdened’ (Hensel, 2005). She goes on: ‘the misleading rhetoric of choice and opportunity has allowed the tort of wrongful birth to garner widespread legal recognition’ (Hensel, 2005). In wrongful birth claims, choice is not entirely the issue and, once again borrowing words from Hensel ‘it is not lost choice in the abstract that is actionable, but the lost opportunity to abort the impaired child or to prevent conception.’ In this light, wrongful birth claims may be ethically problematic. However, the widespread perception that in wrongful birth claims what is at stake is not the value of life (even when disabled) but the price that parents have to pay for bringing up a disabled child, can explain why courts faced with these issues have, generally, rejected wrongful life actions while at the same time approving those for wrongful birth.

Claims relating to ‘wrongful life’ and ‘wrongful birth’ give rise to two questions that are the subject of scientific, ethical and juridical debate. Who is responsible for providing full and correct medical information regarding a developing foetus with serious genetic and congenital disease? Who has the right to receive compensation when a child is born with such a disease (Frati et al., 2014). The themes of ‘wrongful birth’ and ‘wrongful life’ are charged with perplexing ethical dilemmas (Dickens, 1985). They also raise delicate legal questions (i.e. the existence of the right to be born only if healthy or even not to be born at all). These have met, in various countries and on certain occasions, with different solutions and have triggered ethical and juridical debate, arriving at damage case scenarios resulting from a lack of information or diagnosis prior to the birth which deprives the mother of the chance to terminate the pregnancy. The two aspects (the choice of test offered to the expectant mother and the obligation to inform) appear, therefore, to be clearly separate. PD, as described in various documents released by the major scientific bodies, ‘allows for the prevention of the birth of an affected foetus and, where applicable, ensures the best therapy to treat the affected foetus/newborn both in the womb and at birth. Guidelines for genetic tests for PD try to strike a balance between genetic risk, procedural risk and the cost of the service. Disease risk assessment is the role of genetic counselling. Numerous screening techniques are currently used to estimate the risk of a couple having a child with chromosomal or genetic anomalies’ (Italian Society of Ultrasound in Obstetrics and Gynecology, 2015). As for any other medical branch, the type of diagnostic technique used in PD must be appropriate to the type of pathology risk, on the basis of clinical and anamnestic indications. There is no distinction, then, between a life worth and not worth living; instead there is a strong emphasis on the asset of ‘health’, irrespective of the quality of life itself and the subjective perceptions relating to it. Health is understood as being ‘not only in the static dimension of absence from illness, but a dynamic/functional condition of mental and physical wellbeing,’ as the World Health Organization definition suggests. The ‘tragedy’ of a particularly serious disability which is a constitutive part of the child's biography and will be for life, but in no way undermines that child's dignity as a human being, entitles the child and all other family members involved to the fullest compensation. This is quite different from the case of damage to the unborn child which cannot be directly linked to the physician's conduct but for which the compensation claim is based on that condition known as ‘wrongful life’. This covers a range of different situations but particularly, for our interests here, those in which ‘damage’ might have occurred because of the lack of PD, thus depriving the mother of the chance to terminate the pregnancy. The resistance of such events to a rigorous approach intensifies the associated ethical and juridical issues and is reflected in the heightened doctrinal debate which surrounds them. The principle established suggests new frontiers for medical and obstetric decision-making. Clearly, the need to weigh both the benefits and the potential risks of medical procedures should not be disregarded. We would like to stress that the duty to inform should be tempered by maternal desire. The role of information assumes particularly complex meaning when the choice of the mother affects others (the unborn baby or newborn, father, siblings), including the physician whose conduct has influenced this choice (Frati et al., 2014), and the whole society. This regards an increasing number of cases in which the lack of, or wrong, information regarding possible malformations or chromosomal anomalies of the foetus have prevented the pregnant woman from exercising the ‘faculty’ of terminating her pregnancy, thus leading to the birth of a child which is ‘unhealthy’.

Beyond the specific ethical concerns that both wrongful life and wrongful birth claims evoke, damages proximately caused are differently ascertainable in the two claims. A common trait of both wrongful birth and wrongful life claims is that, unlike the traditional medical malpractice case in which negligence directly affects the foetal condition, in these cases the child is disabled or chronically ill regardless of the physician's actions. Wrongful life is more controversial because it identifies the impaired child's life as the operable injury, a concept hard to conceptualize; wrongful birth, on the other hand, seems easier to judge because the injury identified is the parents’ lost choice over the future of the pregnancy and the costs and emotional burden of bearing a disabled child.

But this controversial story continues.

Authors’ roles

All authors contributed equally to article drafting and critical discussion and approved the final version.

Funding

The authors declare no relationship with funding sources or sponsorships.

Conflict of interest

The authors have no conflicts of interest to disclose.

References

Akazaki
L
.
“Wrongful birth”: an ironic name for a cause of action in the law of medical malpractice
.
Advocate's Q
1999
;
22
:
102
108
.

Altarescu
G
,
Beeri
R
,
Lazer-Derbeko
G
,
Eldar-Geva
T
,
Steinberg
A
,
Levy-Lahad
E
,
Renbaum
P
.
Preimplantation genetic risk reduction: a new dilemma in the era of chromosomal microarrays and exome sequencing
.
Reprod Biomed Online
2015
;
31
:
706
710
.

Alvarez
IJ
.
A critique of the motivational analysis in wrongful conception cases
.
Boston Coll Law Rev
2000
;
41
:
585
626
.

Amagwula
T
,
Chang
PL
,
Hossain
A
,
Tyner
J
,
Rivers
AL
,
Phelps
JY
.
Preimplantation genetic diagnosis: a systematic review of litigation in the face of new technology
.
Fertil Steril
2012
;
98
:
1277
1282
.

Arantzazu Vicandi Martínez
D
.
El Concepto De Wrongful Birth Y Su Inherente Problemática
.
REDS
2013
;
3
:
40
59
.

Athanasiadis
AP
,
Polychronou
P
,
Mikos
T
,
Pantazis
K
,
Assimakopoulos
E
,
Tzevelekis
F
,
Bontis
JN
.
Women's expectations and intention to terminate pregnancy in case of abnormal findings at the second trimester level II ultrasound scan. A prospective, questionnaire-based, cross-sectional survey
.
Fetal Diagn Ther
2009
;
25
:
255
263
.

Aurenque
D
.
Genetic diversity as a value: imposing fairness
.
Am J Bioeth
2015
;
15
:
18
20
.

Basille
C
,
Frydman
R
,
El Aly
A
, et al. .
Preimplantation genetic diagnosis: state of the art
.
Eur J Obstet Gynecol Reprod Biol
2009
;
145
:
9
13
.

Beaudet
AL
.
Preimplantation genetic screens
.
Science
2015
;
349
:
1423
.

Beckman
HB
,
Markakis
KM
,
Suchman
AL
,
Frankel
RM
.
The doctor–patient relationship and malpractice. Lessons from plaintiff depositions
.
Arch Intern Med
1994
;
154
:
1365
1370
.

Beller
FK
,
Zlatnik
GP
.
The beginning of human life: medical observations and ethical reflections
.
Clin Obstet Gynecol
1992
;
35
:
720
728
.

Beller
FK
,
Zlatnik
GP
.
The beginning of human life
.
J Assist Reprod Genet
1995
;
12
:
477
483
.

Belsky
AJ
.
Injury as a Matter of Law: is this the Answer to the Wrongful Life Dilemma
. University of Baltimore Law Review, Vol. 22(2),
1993
Art. 3
. http://scholarworks.law.ubalt.edu/ublr/vol22/iss2/3 (2 April 2016, date last accessed).

Bennett
R
.
The fallacy of the principle of procreative beneficence
.
Bioethics
2009
;
23
:
265
273
.

Benagiano
G
,
Mori
M
,
Ford
N
,
Grudzinskas
G
.
Early pregnancy wastage: ethical considerations
.
Reprod Biomed Online
2011
;
22
:
692
700
.

Bennett
R
.
When intuition is not enough. Why the Principle of Procreative Beneficence must work much harder to justify its eugenic vision
.
Bioethics
2014
;
28
:
447
455
.

Berceanu
C
,
Albu
SE
,
Bot
M
,
Ghelase
MS
.
Current principles and practice of ethics and law in perinatal medicine
.
Health Sci J
2014
;
40
:
162
169
.

Bernat
E
.
Informed consent and ‘wrongful birth’: the Austrian Supreme Court's approach
.
Med Law
1992
;
11
:
67
72
.

Bird
S
.
“Wrongful life” claims
.
Aust Fam Phys
2006
;
35
:
633
634
.

Boggio
A
,
Corbellini
G
.
Regulating assisted reproduction in Italy: a 5-year assessment
.
Hum Fertil (Camb)
2009
;
12
:
81
88
.

Botkin
JR
.
The legal concept of wrongful life
.
J Am Med Assoc
1988
;
259
:
1541
1545
.

Botkin
JR
,
Mehlman
MJ
.
Wrongful birth: medical, legal, and philosophical issues
.
J Law Med Ethics
1994
;
22
:
21
28
.

Bottis
MC
.
Wrongful birth and wrongful life actions
.
Eur J Health Law
2004
;
11
:
55
59
.

Brantley
JR
.
Wrongful birth: the emerging status of a new tort
.
St Marys Law J
1976
;
8
:
140
159
.

Brenner
RJ
,
Bartholomew
L
.
Communication errors in radiology: a liability cost analysis
.
J Am Coll Radiol
2005
;
2
:
428
431
.

Brezina
PR
,
Kutteh
WH
.
Clinical applications of preimplantation genetic testing
.
Br Med J
2015
;
350
:
g7611
.

Brezina
PR
,
Kearns
WG
.
The evolving role of genetics in reproductive medicine
.
Obstet Gynecol Clin North Am
2014
;
41
:
41
55
.

Brock
DW
.
The non-identity problem and genetic harms: the case of wrongful handicaps
.
Bioethics
1995
;
9
:
269
275
.

Busardò
FP
,
Gulino
M
,
Napoletano
S
,
Zaami
S
,
Frati
P
.
The evolution of legislation in the field of Medically Assisted Reproduction and embryo stem cell research in European union members
.
Biomed Res Int
2014
;
2014
:
307160
.

Cameron
C
,
Williamson
R
.
Is there an ethical difference between preimplantation genetic diagnosis and abortion
.
J Med Ethics
2003
;
29
:
90
92
.

Capalbo
A
,
Rienzi
L
,
Ubaldi
FM
.
New approaches for multifactor preimplantation genetic diagnosis of monogenic diseases and aneuploidies from a single biopsy
.
Fertil Steril
2016
;
105
:
297
298
.

Capen
K
.
New prenatal screening procedures raise spectre of more “wrongful-birth” claims
.
CMAJ
1995
;
152
:
734
737
.

Carey
KN
.
Wrongful life and wrongful birth: legal aspects of failed genetic testing in oocyte donation
.
Penn Bioeth J
2005
;
1
:
1
4
.

Carmi
A
.
Wrongful life: an Israeli case
.
Med Law
1990
;
9
:
777
781
.

Carmi
A
,
Wax
H
.
Patients’ Rights
.
Yozmot Heiliger, Tel Aviv, Israel
.
2002
,
211
216

Caulfield
T
.
Liability in the genetic era: wrongful birth and wrongful life lawsuits
.
J SOGC
2001
;
23
:
143
147
.

Chadwick
R
,
Childs
R
.
Ethical issues in the diagnosis and management of fetal disorders
.
Best Pract Res Clin Obstet Gynaecol
2012
;
26
:
541
550
.

Chang
J
,
Boulet
SL
,
Jeng
G
,
Flowers
L
,
Kissin
DM
.
Outcomes of in vitro fertilization with preimplantation genetic diagnosis: an analysis of the United States Assisted Reproductive Technology Surveillance Data, 2011–2012
.
Fertil Steril
2016
;
105
:
394
400
.

Chasen
ST
,
Skupski
DW
,
McCullough
LB
,
Chervenak
FA
.
Prenatal informed consent for sonogram: the time for first-trimester nuchal translucency has come
.
J Ultrasound Med
2001
;
20
:
1147
1152
.

Chervenak
FA
,
McCullough
LB
,
Chervenak
JL
.
Prenatal informed consent for sonogram: an indication for obstetric ultrasonography
.
Am J Obstet Gynecol
1989
;
161
:
857
860
.

Chervenak
FA
,
McCullough
LB
.
Ethics of maternal–fetal surgery
.
Semin Fetal Neonatal Med
2007
;
12
:
426
431
.

Chervenak
FA
,
McCullough
LB
.
Ethical issues in perinatal genetics
.
Semin Fetal Neonatal Med
2011
;
16
:
70
73
.

Chima
SC
,
Mamdoo
F
.
Ethical and legal dilemmas around termination of pregnancy for severe fetal anomalies: a review of two African neonates presenting with ventriculomegaly and holoprosencephaly
.
Niger J Clin Pract
2015
;
18
:
S31
S39
.

Cleary
T
.
A curious exception: (no) legal remedies for negligent pre-birth genetic testing
.
J Law Med
2013
;
21
:
102
109
.

Clement
R
,
Rodat
O
.
Post-Perruche: what responsibilities for professionals
.
Med Law
2006
;
25
:
31
43
.

Connors
R
.
Harriton v. Stephens; Waller v. James; Waller v. Hoolahan
.
J Law Med
2005
;
13
:
184
185
.

Cour de Cassation de France
. Assemblée plénière. Arr êt du 17 novembre
2000
. https://www.legifrance.gouv.fr/affichJuriJudi.do?idTexte=JURITEXT000007041543 (2 April 2016, date last accessed).

Court for the District of Columbia
. Hartke v. McKelway 526 F. Supp.97 D.D.C.
1981
.

Court for the Southern District of West Virginia
. Whittington v. Eli Lilly 333 F. Supp. 98, S.D.W. Va. 1971 November 5; Munson, 1975; Brantley, 1976.

Court of Appeal of Brussels
, no. 14675/2010. http://religaredatabase.cnrs.fr/spip.php?article148.

Court of Appeal for Ontario.

Bovington v. Hergott
, January
2008
. http://www.ontariocourts.on.ca/decisions/2008/january/2008ONCA0002.html (2 April 2016, date last accessed).

Court of Illinois
.
Clark v. Children's Memorial Hospital
, 955 N.E.2d 1065.
2011
.

Court of South Africa.

Friedman v. Glicksman
SA 1134 (W)
1996
.

Crockin
SL
.
Ethics, legal, social, counselling reproduction, genetics and the law
.
Reprod Biomed Online
2005
;
10
:
692
704
.

Daly
B
.
Wrongful birth, wrongful conception, and the Irish Constitution
.
Eur J Health Law
2005
;
12
:
57
76
.

de Angel Yágüez
R
.
With the fourth sentence of the First Chamber on wrongful birth: is it possible to start talking about “jurisprudence”
.
Rev Derecho Genoma Hum
2005
;
22
:
179
206
.

de Jong
A
,
Maya
I
,
van Lith
JM
.
Prenatal screening: current practice, new developments, ethical challenges
.
Bioethics
2015
;
29
:
1
8
.

de Jong
A
,
de Wert
GM
.
Prenatal screening: an ethical agenda for the near future
.
Bioethics
2015
;
29
:
46
55
.

de Reuver
PR
,
Wind
J
,
Cremers
JE
,
Busch
OR
,
van Gulik
TM
,
Gouma
DJ
.
Litigation after laparoscopic cholecystectomy: an evaluation of the Dutch arbitration system for medical malpractice
.
J Am Coll Surg
2008
;
206
:
328
334
.

deWert
G
Ethics of assisted reproduction. In:
Fauser
BCJM
(ed).
Reproductive Medicine. Molecular, Cellular and Genetic Fundamentals
.
Boca Raton, FL
:
Parthenon
,
2002
;
645
665
.

de Wert
G
.
Preimplantation genetic diagnosis: the ethics of intermediate cases
.
Hum Reprod
2005
;
20
:
3261
3266
.

de Wert
G
,
Dondorp
W
,
Shenfield
F
,
Devroey
P
,
Tarlatzis
B
,
Barri
P
,
Diedrich
K
,
Provoost
V
,
Pennings
G
.
ESHRE Task Force on Ethics and Law22: preimplantation genetic diagnosis
.
Hum Reprod
2014
;
29
:
1610
1617
.

Deans
Z
,
Clarke
AJ
,
Newson
AJ
.
For your interest? The ethical acceptability of using non-invasive prenatal testing to test ‘purely for information’
.
Bioethics
2015
;
29
:
19
25
.

DeGrazia
D
.
Creation ethics: reproduction, genetics and quality of life
.
J Med Ethics
2015
;
41
:
415
416
.

Deprest
J
,
Toelen
J
,
Debyser
Z
,
Rodrigues
C
,
Devlieger
R
,
De Catte
L
,
Lewi
L
,
Van Mieghem
T
,
Naulaers
G
,
Vandevelde
M
et al. .
The fetal patient—ethical aspects of fetal therapy
.
Facts Views Vis Obgyn
2011
;
3
:
221
227
.

Devereux
J
.
Wrongful death claims. Harriton v. Stephens. [2002] NSWSC 461. Edwards v. Blomeley. [2002] NSWSC 460. Waller v. James [2002] NSWSC 462
.
J Law Med
2002
;
10
:
163
167
.

Devisch
I
.
The tribunal of modern life: the case of UZ Brussels in the light of Odo Marquard's discussion on autonomy and theodicy
.
J Eval Clin Pract
2013
;
19
:
471
477
.

Dickens
BM
.
The dilemma of wrongful birth, wrongful life. Interview by Bill trent
.
CMAJ
1985
;
133
:
1238
1240
.

Dickens
BM
,
Cook
RJ
.
Ethical and legal approaches to ‘the fetal patient’
.
Int J Gynaecol Obstet
2003
;
83
:
85
91
.

Dickens
BM
,
Cook
RJ
.
Legal and ethical issues in fetal surgery
.
Int J Gynaecol Obstet
2011
;
115
:
80
83
.

Dimopoulos
P
,
Bagaric
M
.
The moral status of wrongful life claims
.
Common Law World Rev
2003
;
32
:
35
64
.

Dimopoulos
P
,
Bagaric
M
.
Why wrongful birth actions are right
.
J Law Med
2003
;
11
:
230
238
.

DiSilvestro
R
.
Reproductive autonomy, the non-identity problem, and the non-person problem
.
Bioethics
2009
;
23
:
59
67
.

Domröse
CM
,
Bremer
S
,
Buczek
C
,
Geipel
A
,
Berg
C
,
Gembruch
U
,
Willruth
A
.
Termination of pregnancy after prenatal diagnosis of spina bifida: a German perspective
.
Arch Gynecol Obstet
2016
;
294
:
731
737
.

Dondorp
W
,
de Wert
G
.
Innovative reproductive technologies: risks and responsibilities
.
Hum Reprod
2011
;
26
:
1604
1608
.

Dondorp
W
,
van Lith
J
.
Dynamics of prenatal screening: new developments challenging the ethical framework
.
Bioethics
2015
;
29
:
ii
iv
.

Dorozynski
A
.
Highest French court awards compensation for “being born”
.
Br Med J
2001
;
323
:
1384
.

Drgonec
J
.
The status of the foetus
.
Med Law
1994
;
13
:
215
239
.

Druzin
ML
,
Chervenak
F
,
McCullough
LB
,
Blatman
RN
,
Neidich
JA
.
Should all pregnant patients be offered prenatal diagnosis regardless of age
.
Obstet Gynecol
1993
;
81
:
615
618
.

DuBois
JM
.
Prenatal genetic testing and wrongful birth lawsuits
.
Health Care Ethics USA
2001
;
9
:
E1
.

Dunstan
GR
.
The moral status of the human embryo: a tradition recalled
.
J Med Ethics
1984
;
10
:
38
44
.

Durland
U
.
Preimplantation genetic diagnosis and screening
.
J Obstet Gynaecol Can
2015
;
37
:
686
.

Dutch Federal Court of Justice
. 86 BGHZ 240–1983 38 JZ 447, 18th January
1983
.

Eagan
MN
.
Hall v Dartmouth Hitchcock Medical Center
.
USA
:
West Publishing
,
2006
,
240
249
.

El-Toukhy
,
Williams
C
,
Braude
P
.
The ethics of preimplantation genetic diagnosis, The ethics of preimplantation genetic diagnosis
.
Obstet Gynaecol
2011
;
10
:
1
(version of Record online: 24 Jan).

European Court of Human Rights, Vo v. France
(
2004
) ECHR 326, no. 84. http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-61887#{“itemid”:[“001-61887”]} (2 April 2016, date last accessed).

Evgenia
S
.
Wrongful Life And Birth
.
Med Law
2012
;
31
:
97
118
.

Ewigman
B
,
LeFevre
M
,
Bain
RP
,
Crane
JP
,
McNellis
D
.
Ethics and routine ultrasonography in pregnancy
.
Am J Obstet Gynecol
1990
;
163
:
256
258
.

Faunce
T
,
Jefferys
S
.
Abandoning the common law: medical negligence, genetic tests and wrongful life in the Australian High Court
.
J Law Med
2007
;
14
:
469
477
.

Feinberg
J
.
Harm to Others
.
New York
:
Oxford University Press
,
1984
,
102
.

Feinberg
J
.
Wrongful life and the counterfactual element in harming
.
Soc Philos Policy
1986
;
4
:
145
178
.

Fisher
CW
,
Witty
LL
.
Medicolegal genetic issues
.
Clin Perinatol
2001
;
28
:
463
476
.

Flagler
E
,
Baylis
F
,
Rodgers
S
.
Bioethics for clinicians: 12. Ethical dilemmas that arise in the care of pregnant women: rethinking “maternal-fetal conflicts”
.
CMAJ
1997
;
156
:
1729
1732
.

Francis
L
.
Creation Ethics and the harms of existence
.
J Med Ethics
2015
;
41
:
418
419
.

Frati
P
,
Gulino
M
,
Turillazzi
E
,
Zaami
S
,
Fineschi
V
.
The physician's breach of the duty to inform the parent of deformities and abnormalities in the foetus: “wrongful life” actions, a new frontier of medical responsibility
.
J Matern Fetal Neonatal Med
2014
;
27
:
1113
1117
.

Gaille
M
.
On prenatal diagnosis and the decision to continue or terminate a pregnancy in France: a clinical ethics study of unknown moral territories
.
Med Health Care Philos
2016
;
19
:
381
391
.

Gebhart
MB
,
Hines
RS
,
Penman
A
,
Holland
AC
.
How do patient perceived determinants influence the decision-making process to accept or decline preimplantation genetic screening
.
Fertil Steril
2016
;
105
:
188
193
.

Gekas
J
,
Langlois
S
,
Ravitsky
V
,
Audibert
F
,
van den Berg
DG
,
Haidar
H
,
Rousseau
F
.
Non-invasive prenatal testing for fetal chromosome abnormalities: review of clinical and ethical issues
.
Appl Clin Genet
2016
;
9
:
15
26
.

Giesen
D
.
A comparative study of civil liability arising from medical care
.
International Medical Malpractice Law JCB Low
1988
:
247
248
.

Giesen
I
. Of wrongful birth, wrongful life, comparative law and the politics of tort law systems. Rhodes University,
2008
. http://www.ivogiesen.com/media/1068/giesen_thrhr_2009.pdf.

Giesen
I
.
The use and influence of comparative law in ‘wrongful life’ cases
.
Utrecht Law Rev
2012
;
8
:
35
54
.

Gillon
R
.
‘Wrongful life’ claims
.
J Med Ethics
1998
;
24
:
363
364
.

Gordon
A.
2012
New Zealand Supreme Court considers a case of medical misadventure, unexpected pregnancy, personal injury and the Accident Compensation Act. Australian Health Law Bulletin, 20.

Grady
MF
.
Better medicine causes more lawsuits, and new administrative courts will not solve the problem
.
Nw U L Rev
1992
;
86
:
1068
1071
.

Gulino
M
,
Pacchiarotti
A
,
Vergallo
GM
,
Frati
P
.
Is age the limit for human-assisted reproduction techniques? ‘Yes’, said an Italian judge
.
J Med Ethics
2013
;
39
:
250
252
.

Gur
N
.
Wrongful life claims and negligent selection of gametes or embryos in infertility treatments: a quest for coherence
.
J Law Med
2014
;
22
:
426
441
.

Hafner
E
.
Wrongful birth—a step in the right direction
.
Ultraschall Med
2011
;
32
:
107
108
.

Harlan
H
.
Feminist perspectives, disability, sexuality and law: new issues and agendas
.
S Cal Rev L Women's Stud
1994
;
97
.

Harper
J
,
Geraedts
J
,
Borry
P
,
Cornel
MC
,
Dondorp
WJ
,
Gianaroli
L
,
Harton
G
,
Milachich
T
,
Kääriäinen
H
,
Liebaers
I
, et al. .
ESHG, ESHRE and EuroGentest2. Current issues in medically assisted reproduction and genetics in Europe: research, clinical practice, ethics, legal issues and policy
.
Hum Reprod
2014
;
29
:
1603
1609
.

Hassan
M
,
Chitty
L
,
Reardon
H
.
Wrongful birth: clinical settings and legal implications
.
Semin Fetal Neonatal Med
2014
;
19
:
312
316
.

Hens
K
,
Dondorp
W
,
Handyside
AH
,
Harper
J
,
Newson
AJ
,
Pennings
G
,
Rehmann-Sutter
C
,
de Wert
G
.
Dynamics and ethics of comprehensive preimplantation genetic testing: a review of the challenges
.
Hum Reprod Update
2013
;
19
:
366
375
.

Hensel
WF
.
The disabling impact of wrongful birth and wrongful life actions
.
Harv Civ Rights-Civil Lib Law Rev
2005
;
40
:
144
145
.

Hewison
J.
Psychological aspects of individualized choice and reproductive autonomy in prenatal screening
.
Bioethics
2015
;
29
:
9
18
.

Hickson
GB
,
Clayton
EW
,
Entman
SS
,
Miller
CS
,
Githens
PB
,
Whetten-Goldstein
K
,
Sloan
FA
.
Obstetricians’ prior malpractice experience and patients’ satisfaction with care
.
JAMA
1994
;
272
:
1583
1587
.

High Court of Australia
, Harriton v Stephens, HCA 15,
2006
.

Howlett
MJ
,
Avard
D
,
Knoppers
BM
.
Physicians and genetic malpractice
.
Med Law
2002
;
21
:
661
680
.

Hu
X
,
Wang
J
,
Li
Y
,
Wang
Y
,
Ding
C
,
Zeng
Y
,
Xu
Y
,
Zhou
C
.
Clinical considerations of preimplantation genetic diagnosis for monogenic diseases
.
PLoS One
2015
;
10
:
e0139613
.

Hunt
LM
,
de Voogd
KB
,
Castaneda
H
.
The routine and the traumatic in prenatal genetic diagnosis: does clinical information inform patient decision-making
.
Patient Educ Couns
2005
;
56
:
302
312
.

Hurley
CT
,
McKenna
MR
.
Wrongful Birth
.
Ill Bar J
2013
;
101
:
1
5
.

Irion
NF
,
Irion
O
.
Introduction in Switzerland of preimplantation genetic testing: progress or downward spiral
.
Rev Med Suisse
2016
;
12
:
(39–40, 42-43)
.

Isaacs
D
.
Moral status of the fetus: fetal rights or maternal autonomy
.
J Paediatr Child Health
2003
;
39
:
58
59
.

Israeli Supreme Court, Hammer v Amit, C.A. 1326/07
,
2012
.

Italian Society of Ultrasound in Obstetrics and Gynecology
, Guidelines
2015
.

Italian Supreme Court, Judgement no. 25767 of 22nd December
2015
. http://www.neldiritto.it/appgiurisprudenza.asp?id=12072 (2 April 2016, date last accessed).

Jackson
A
,.
Action for wrongful life, wrongful pregnancy, and wrongful birth in the United States and England
,
Loy LA Intl Comp L Rev
1995
;
17
:
535,543, 544
.

Jackson
A
.
Wrongful life and wrongful birth. The English conception
.
J Leg Med
1996
;
17
:
349
381
.

Jankowski
KJ
.
Wrongful birth and wrongful life actions arising from negligent genetic counseling: the need for legislation supporting reproductive choice
.
Fordham Urb L J
1989
;
17
:
30
31
.

Jecker
NS
.
The right not to be born: reinterpreting the nonidentity problem
.
Am J Bioeth
2012
;
12
:
34
35
.

Jha
S
.
‘Wrongful Birth’ following failed sterilization
.
BJOG
2016
;
123
:
1683
. .

Jones
GE
,
Perry
C
.
Can claims for ‘wrongful life’ be justified
.
J Med Ethics
1983
;
9
. 162-4, 174.

Jonsen
AR
.
Women's choices—the ethics of maternity
.
West J Med
1988
;
149
:
726
728
.

Juristische Blatter
.
1991
;113:316.

Kapteiran
G
.
Harriton, Waller And Australian negligence law: is there a place for wrongful life
.
J Law Med
2006
;
13
:
334
351
.

Kearl
KJ
.
Turpin v. Sortini: recognizing the unsupportable cause of action for wrongful life
.
Calif Law Rev
1983
;
71
:
1278
1297
.

Kelly
MB
.
The rightful position in “wrongful life” actions
.
Hastings Law J
1991
;
42
:
505
590
.

Kennedy
B
.
The trend toward judicial recognition of wrongful life: a dissenting view
.
UCLA Law Rev
1983
;
31
:
473
501
.

Klein
RD
,
Mahoney
MJ
.
Medical legal issues in prenatal diagnosis
.
Clin Perinatol
2007
;
34
:
287
297
.

Knoppers
BM
,
Bordet
S
,
Isasi
RM
.
Preimplantation genetic diagnosis: an overview of socio-ethical and legal considerations
.
Annu Rev Genomics Hum Genet
2006
;
7
:
201
221
.

Kose
S
,
Altunyurt
S
,
Yıldırım
N
,
Keskinoğlu
P
,
Çankaya
T
,
Bora
E
,
Erçal
D
,
Özer
E
.
Termination of pregnancy for fetal abnormalities: main arguments and a decision-tree model
.
Prenat Diagn
2015
;
35
:
1128
1136
.

Kurjak
A
,
Tripalo
A
.
The facts and doubts about the beginning of human life and personality
.
J Matern Fetal Neonatal Med
2003
;
14
:
361
369
.

Kushnir
VA
,
Darmon
SK
,
Albertini
DF
,
Barad
DH
,
Gleicher
N
.
Effectiveness of in vitro fertilization with preimplantation genetic screening: a reanalysis of United States assisted reproductive technology data 2011–2012
.
Fertil Steril
2016
;
106
:
75
79
.

Lakhoo
K
.
Fetal counselling for surgical conditions
.
Early Hum Dev
2012
;
88
:
9
13
.

Laufer
JA
.
Medical malpractice: wrongful life—Turpin v. Sortini, 31 Cal.3d 220, 643 P.2d 954, 182 Cal. Rptr. 337 (1982)
.
Akron Law Rev
1982
;
16
:
313
323
.

Lenke
RR
,
Nemes
JM
.
Wrongful birth, wrongful life: the doctor between a rock and a hard place
.
Obstet Gynecol
1985
;
66
:
719
722
.

Levi
J
.
Wrongful life decision in Israel. Civil appeal 518/82, 540/82
.
Med Law
1987
;
6
:
373
374
.

Levinson
W
,
Roter
DL
,
Mullooly
JP
,
Dull
VT
,
Frankel
RM
.
Physician–patient communication. The relationship with malpractice claims among primary care physicians and surgeons
.
J Am Med Assoc
1997
;
277
:
553
559
.

Liu
AN
.
Wrongful life: some of the problems
.
J Med Ethics
1987
;
13
:
69
73
.

Localio
AR
,
Lawthers
AG
,
Brennan
TA
,
Laird
NM
,
Hebert
LE
,
Peterson
LM
,
Newhouse
JP
,
Weilwe
PC
,
Hiatt
HH
.
Relation between malpractice claims and adverse events due to negligence. Results of the Harvard Medical Practice Study III
.
N Engl J Med
1991
;
325
:
245
251
.

Loi Kouchner
no. 2002-303 March, 4,
2002
. https://www.legifrance.gouv.fr/affichTexte.do?cidTexte=JORFTEXT000000227015&categorieLien=id (2 April 2016, date last accessed).

London Royal Courts of Justice
. Rees v. Darlington Memorial Hospital NHS Trust;
2003
:UKHL 52.

Loukogeorgakis
SP
,
Flake
AW
.
In utero stem cell and gene therapy: current status and future perspectives
.
Eur J Pediatr Surg
2014
;
24
:
237
245
.

Lowther
C
,
Costain
G
,
Bassett
AS
.
Reproductive genetic testing and human genetic variation in the era of genomic medicine
.
Am J Bioeth
2015
;
15
:
25
26
.

Mahowald
MB
Women and Children in Health Care: An Unequal Majority
.
New York
:
Oxford University Press
,
1993
;
131
143
.

Malek
J
.
Deciding against disability: does the use of reproductive genetic technologies express disvalue for people with disabilities
.
J Med Ethics
2010
;
36
:
217
221
.

Manaouil
C
,
Gignon
M
,
Jardé
O
.
10 years of controversy, twists and turns in the Perruche wrongful life claim: compensation for children born with a disability in France
.
Med Law
2012
;
31
:
661
669
.

Manaouil
C
,
Jardè
O
.
Is there still a future for the French “Perruche” jurisprudence
.
Gynecol Obstet Fertil
2012
;
40
:
71
76
.

Markesinis
BS
,
Unberath
U
. The German Law of Torts: A Comparative Treatise, 4th edn, 2002; 162 –179. Hart Publishing, Kemp House, Chawley Park, Cumnor Hill, Oxford, UK.

Maryland Court of Special Appeals
. Kassama v. Magat.
West's Atl Report
2001
;
767
:
348
369
.

Maxwell
S
,
Bower
C
,
O'Leary
P
.
Impact of prenatal screening and diagnostic testing on trends in Down syndrome births and terminations in Western Australia 1980 to 2013
.
Prenat Diagn
2015
;
35
:
1324
1330
.

McClain
LE
,
Flake
AW
.
In utero stem cell transplantation and gene therapy: recent progress and the potential for clinical application
.
Best Pract Res Clin Obstet Gynaecol
2016
;
31
:
88
98
.

McMahan
J
.
The morality of screening for disability
.
Reprod Biomed Online
2005
;
10
:
129
132
.

McMann
CL
,
Carter
BS
,
Lantos
JD
.
Ethical issues in fetal diagnosis and treatment
.
Am J Perinatol
2014
;
31
:
637
644
.

Menahem
S
,
Grimwade
J
.
Pregnancy termination following prenatal diagnosis of serious heart disease in the fetus
.
Early Hum Dev
2003
;
73
:
71
78
.

Mertes
H
,
Hens
K
.
The diversity of genetic perfection
.
Am J Bioeth
2015
;
15
:
34
36
.

Molenaar
JC
.
The legal investigation of a decision not to operate on an infant with Down's syndrome and a duodenal atresia: a report from the Netherlands
.
Bioethics
1992
;
6
:
35
40
.

Molinelli
A
,
Bonsignore
A
,
Darretta
V
,
Anserini
P
.
Results and unsolved problems following the amendment to the Italian Law on assisted reproduction brought about by the Constitutional Court
.
Eur J Obstet Gynecol Reprod Biol
2012
;
163
:
1
4
.

Moore
MM
.
Wrongful birth—the problem of damage computation
.
UMKC Law Rev
1979
;
48
:
1
14
.

Mor
S
.
The dialectics of wrongful life and wrongful birth claims in Israel: a disability critique
.
Stud Law Polit Soc
2014
;
63
:
113
146
.

Morris
A
,
Saintier
S
.
To be or not to be: is that the question? Wrongful life and misconceptions
.
Med Law Rev
2003
;
11
:
167
193
.

Munson
JW
.
Fetal research: a view from right to life to wrongful birth
.
Chic Kent Law Rev
1975
;
52
:
133
156
.

Munthe
C
.
A new ethical landscape of prenatal testing: individualizing choice to serve autonomy and promote public health: a radical proposal
.
Bioethics
2015
;
29
:
36
45
.

Muriithi
PM
.
Does the rejection of wrongful life claims rely on a conceptual error
.
J Med Ethics
2011
;
37
:
433
436
.

Nagel
T
.
Applied Ethics—Death
1st edn
USA
,
Singer, Oxford Readings in Philosophy
,
1986
.

New South Wales Court of Appeal
, Waller v James, NSWCA 232,
2015
.

Noble
R
,
Rodeck
CH
.
Ethical considerations of fetal therapy
.
Best Pract Res Clin Obstet Gynaecol
2008
;
22
:
219
231
.

Nys
HF
,
Dute
JC
.
A wrongful existence in the Netherlands
.
J Med Ethics
2004
;
30
:
393
394
.

O'Brien
P
,
Nugent
M
,
Khalil
A
.
Prenatal diagnosis and obstetric management
.
Semin Pediatr Surg
2015
;
24
:
203
206
.

Parens
E.
,
Asch
A
.
Disability rights critique of prenatal genetic testing: reflections and recommendations
.
Ment Retard Dev Disabil Res Rev
2003
;
9
:
40
47
.

Parfit
D
.
Reasons and Persons
.
Oxford
:
Oxford Clarendon Press
,
1984
.

Pattinson
SD
.
Wrongful life actions as a means of regulating use of genetic and reproductive technologies
.
Health Law J
1999
;
7
:
19
32
.

Pelias
MZ
.
Torts of wrongful birth and wrongful life: a review
.
Am J Med Genet
1986
;
25
:
71
80
.

Pennsylvania Supreme Court
. Speck v. Finegold 497 pa. 77 439 a. 2d 110.
1981
.

Pergament
D
,
Ilijic
K
.
The legal past, present and future of prenatal genetic testing: professional liability and other legal challenges affecting patient access to services
.
J Clin Med
2014
;
3
:
1437
1465
.

Perry
R
.
It's a wonderful life: is it possible to say that a severely disabled child has been harmed by the mere fact of being born
.
Cornell Law Rev
2007
;
93
:
329
400
.

Petersen
K
.
Medical negligence and wrongful birth actions: Australian developments
.
J Med Ethics
1997
;
23
:
319
322
.

Petersen
TS
.
Just diagnosis? Preimplantation genetic diagnosis and injustices to disabled people
.
J Med Ethics
2005
;
31
:
231234
.

Petersen
TS
.
On the partiality of procreative beneficence: a critical note
.
J Med Ethics
2015
;
41
:
771
774
.

Pioro
M
,
Mykitiuk
R
,
Nisker
J
.
Wrongful birth litigation and prenatal screening
.
CMAJ
2008
;
179
:
1027
1030
.

Propping
P
,
Schott
H
.
Embryo screening: update German view of genetic testing
.
Nature
2014
;
510
:
473
.

Queen's Bench
, McKay v Essex Area Health Authority, 1 QB 1166,
1982
.

Rafi
I
,
Chitty
L
.
Cell-free fetal DNA and non-invasive prenatal testing
.
Br J Gen Pract
2009
;
59
:
e146
e148
.

Rakowski
E
.
Who should pay for bad genes
.
Calif Law Rev
2002
;
90
:
1345
1414
.

Reuter
L
.
Human is what is born of a human: personhood, rationality, and an European convention
.
J Med Philos
2000
;
25
:
181
194
.

Ricci
G
,
Delbon
P
,
Conti
A
,
Sirignano
A
.
Literature review and state of the art of the Italian law on medically assisted reproduction
.
Clin Ter
2015
;
166
:
e234
e241
.

Rinaldi
JA
.
Wrongful life and wrongful birth: the devaluation of life with disability
.
J Public Health Pol
2009
;
1
:
1
7
.

Robertson
JA
.
Extending preimplantation genetic diagnosis: medical and non-medical uses
.
J Med Ethics
2003
;
29
:
213
216
.

Robertson
JA
.
Ethics and the future of preimplantation genetic diagnosis
.
Reprod Biomed Online
2005
;
10
:
97
101
.

Rodriguez-Purata
J
,
Lee
J
,
Whitehouse
M
,
Moschini
RM
,
Knopman
J
,
Duke
M
,
Sandler
B
,
Copperman
A
.
Embryo selection versus natural selection: how do outcomes of comprehensive chromosome screening of blastocysts compare with the analysis of products of conception from early pregnancy loss (dilation and curettage) among an assisted reproductive technology population
.
Fertil Steril
2015
;
104
:
1460
1466
.

Roberts
MA
.
Can it ever be better never to have existed at all? Person-based consequentialism and a new repugnant conclusion
.
J Appl Philos
2003
;
20
:
159
185
.

Roth
R
.
Congenital disabilities and the law
.
Clin Perinatol
2007
;
34
:
263
273
.

Sakaihara
M
.
Wrongful birth claim in Japan
.
Med Sci Law
2002
;
42
:
258
260
.

Sakaihara
M
.
Claims made by children in Japan for injuries caused before birth
.
Med Sci Law
2007
;
47
:
61
63
.

Savulescu
J
.
Procreative beneficence: why we should select the best children
.
Bioethics
2001
;
15
:
413
426
.

Savulescu
J
.
Is there a “right not to be born”? Reproductive decision making, options and the right to information
.
J Med Ethics
2002
;
28
:
65
67
.

Savulescu
J
.
In defence of procreative beneficence
.
J Med Ethics
2007
;
33
:
284
288
.

Savulescu
J
,
Kahane
G
.
The moral obligation to create children with the best chance of the best life
.
Bioethics
2009
;
23
:
274
290
.

Schenker
JG
.
The beginning of human life. Status of embryo. Perspectives in Halakha (Jewish Religious Law)
.
J Assist Reprod Genet
2008
;
25
:
271
276
.

Schmidt
SM
.
Wrongful life
.
J Am Med Assoc
1983
;
250
:
2209
2210
.

Schmitz
D
,
Netzer
C
,
Henn
W
.
An offer you can't refuse? Ethical implications of non-invasive prenatal diagnosis
.
Nat Rev Genet
2009
;
10
:
515
.

Shannon
TA
.
Fetal status: sources and implications
.
J Med Philos
1997
;
22
:
415
422
.

Shapira
A
.
‘Wrongful life’ lawsuits for faulty genetic counselling: should the impaired newborn be entitled to sue
.
J Med Ethics
1998
;
24
:
369
375
.

Sharman
R
.
Wrongful life actions: the legal and ethical hurdles
.
J Law Med
2001
;
9
:
233
237
.

Shaw
J
.
Wrongful birth and the politics of reproduction: West German and English law considered
.
Int J Law Fam
1990
;
4
:
52
82
.

Shea
MC
.
Embryonic life and human life
.
J Med Ethics
1985
;
11
:
205
209
.

Sheldon
T
.
Court awards damages to disabled child for having been born
.
Br Med J
2003
;
326
:
784
.

Sheldon
T
.
Dutch Supreme Court backs damages for child for having been born
.
Br Med J
2005
;
330
:
747
.

Sijmons
RH
,
Van Langen
IM
,
Sijmons
JG
.
A clinical perspective on ethical issues in genetic testing
.
Account Res
2011
;
18
:
148
162
.

Soini
S
,
Ibarreta
D
,
Anastasiadou
V
,
Aymé
S
,
Braga
S
,
Cornel
M
,
Coviello
DA
,
Evers-Kiebooms
G
,
Geraedts
J
,
Gianaroli
L
et al. .
The interface between assisted reproductive technologies and genetics: technical, social, ethical and legal issues
.
Eur J Hum Genet
2006
;
14
:
588
645
.

Sõritsa
D
,
Lahe
J
.
The possibility of compensation for damages in cases of wrongful conception, wrongful birth and wrongful life. An Estonian perspective
.
Eur J Health Law
2014
;
21
:
141
160
.

South Africa Supreme Court of Appeal
, Stewart and Another v Botha and Another, 340/07,
2008
.

Steinbock
B
.
The logical case for “wrongful life”
.
Hastings Cent Rep
1986
;
16
:
15
20
.

Steinbock
B
.
Maternal–fetal conflict and in utero fetal therapy
.
Albany Law Rev
1994
;
57
:
782
793
.

Steinbock
B.
Preimplantation genetic diagnosis and embryo selection. In:
Burley
J
,
Harris
J
(eds).
A Companion to Genethics
.
Malden, USA/Oxford, UK
:
Blackwell
,
2002
,
147
157
.

Steinbock
B
. Wrongful life and procreative decisions. In:
Harming Future Persons
;
Vol. 35
.
Netherlands, NE
:
Springer Netherlands
,
2009
;
155
178
.

Strauss
SA
.
‘Wrongful conception’, ‘wrongful birth’ and ‘wrongful life’: the first South African cases
.
Med Law
1996
;
15
:
161
173
.

Stretton
D
.
The birth torts: damages for wrongful birth and wrongful life
.
Deakin Law Rev
2005
;
10
:
319
364
.

Stretton
D
.
Wrongful life and the logic of non-existence
.
Melbourne U L Rev
2006
;
30
:
972
1001
.

Strong
C
.
Fetal anomalies: ethical and legal considerations in screening, detection, and management
.
Clin Perinatol
2003
;
30
:
113
126
.

Sullivan
MB
.
Wrongful birth and wrongful conception: a parent's need for a cause of action
.
J Law Health
2000
;
15
:
105
120
.

Supreme Court of California
. Turpin v. Sortini 643 P.2d at 963.
1982
.

Supreme Court of Illinois
. Zepeda v. Zepeda 41 Ill. App.2d 240, 190 N.E.2d 849.
1963
.

Supreme Court of New Hampshire
. Hall v. Dartmouth Hitchcock Medical Center,
2006
.

Supreme Court of New Jersey
. Berman v. Allan 404 A.2d 8 NJ.
1979
.

Thomas
CM
.
Claims for Wrongful Pregnancy and Child Rearing Expenses
.
Massey University Discussion Paper series
2002
;ISSN 1175-2874

Tobin
R
.
Wrongful birth in New Zealand
.
J Law Med
2005
;
12
:
294
304
.

Toews
M
,
Caulfield
T
.
Physician liability and non-invasive prenatal testing
.
J Obstet Gynaecol Can
2014
;
36
:
907
914
.

Tribunal Supremo
, Sentencia de 16 Jun
2010
, rec. 4403/2008. http://agadesa.com/tribunal-supremo-sala-tercera-de-lo-contencioso-administrativo-seccion-4a-sentencia-de-16-jun-2010-rec-44032008/ (2 April 2016, date last accessed).

Tucker
JL
.
Wrongful life: a new generation
.
J Fam Law
1988
–1989;
27
:
673
696
.

Turillazzi
E
,
Fineschi
V
.
Preimplantation genetic diagnosis: a step by step guide to recent Italian ethical and legislative troubles
.
J Med Ethics
2008
;
34
:
e21
.

Turillazzi
E
,
Neri
M
,
Riezzo
I
,
Frati
P
,
Fineschi
V
.
Informed consent in Italy-traditional versus the law: a gordian knot
.
Aesthetic Plast Surg
2014
;
38
:
759
764
.

Turillazzi
E
,
Frati
P
,
Busardò
FP
,
Gulino
M
,
Fineschi
V
.
The European Court legitimates access of Italian couples to assisted reproductive techniques and to pre-implantation genetic diagnosis
.
Med Sci Law
2015
;
55
:
194
200
.

Uberoi
D
,
de Bruyn
M
.
Human rights versus legal control over women's reproductive self-determination
.
Health Hum Rights
2013
;
15
:
E161
E174
.

Um
YR
.
A critique of a ‘wrongful life’ lawsuit in Korea
.
Nurs Ethics
2000
;
7
:
250
261
.

U.S. District Court for the Western District of Oklahoma
, Liddington v. Burns, 916 F. Supp. 1127,
1995
.

VanDerhoef
PJ
.
Washington recognizes wrongful birth and wrongful life: a critical analysis – Harbeson v. Parke-Davis, Inc., 98 Wn.2d 460, 656 P.2d 483
.
Wash Law Rev
1983
;
58
:
649
678
.

van Gerven
W
,
Lever
J
,
Larouche
P
.
Tort law
, 1st edn.
UK
:
Hart Publishing
,
2001
;
82
83
.

Ventura-Juncá
P
,
Santos
MJ
.
The beginning of life of a new human being from the scientific biological perspective and its bioethical implications
.
Biol Res
2011
;
44
:
201
207
.

Ville
Y
.
Fetal therapy: practical ethical considerations
.
Prenat Diagn
2011
;
31
:
621
627
.

Viney
G
,
Jourdain
P
.
Traité de droit civil
.
Les conditions de la responsabilite
2006
;
249
252
. LGDJ, Paris, France.

Virginia Supreme Court
. Naccash v. Burger 223 Va. 406, 290 S.E. 2d 825.
1982
.

Wald
N
.
First-trimester nuchal translucency screening
.
J Ultrasound Med
2002
;
21
:
481
.

Wasserman
D
.
Disability, diversity, and preference for the status quo: bias or justifiable preference
.
Am J Bioeth
2015
;
15
:
11
12
.

Watt
H
.
The Ethics of Pregnancy, Abortion and Childbirth: Exploring Moral Choices in Childbearing
, 1st edn.
London, UK
:
Routledge, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews
,
2016
.

Webster
A
.
Innovative health technologies and the social: health, medicine and the body
.
Curr Sociol
2002
;
50
:
443
457
.

Whetstine
LM
.
Ethical challenges in assisted reproduction: the place of preimplantation genetic diagnosis in a just society
.
J Child Neurol
2015
;
30
:
547
550
.

Whitney
DW
,
Rosenbaum
KN
.
Recovery of damages for wrongful birth
.
J Leg Med
2011
;
32
:
167
204
.

Wilkinson
S
.
Prenatal screening, reproductive choice, and public health
.
Bioethics
2015
;
29
:
26
35
.

Winiger
B
,
Koziol
H
,
Koch
BA
,
Zimmermann
R
Digest of European Tort Law. Volume 2: Essential Cases on Demage
.
Berlin/Boston
:
Walter de Gruyter GmbH&Co. KG
,
2011
;
956
957
.

Wright
CF
,
Chitty
LS
.
Cell-free fetal DNA and RNA in maternal blood: implications for safer antenatal testing
.
Br Med J
2009
;
339
:
b2451
.

Yeo
GS
,
Lim
ML
.
Maternal and fetal best interests in day-to-day obstetrics
.
Ann Acad Med Singapore
2011
;
40
:
43
49
.

Young
R
.
Wrongful life claim: Harriton (by her tutor) v. Stephens; Waller (by his tutor) v. James; Waller (by his tutor) v. Hoolahan
.
J Law Med
2004
;
12
:
17
25
.

Zuradzki
T
.
Preimplantation genetic diagnosis and rational choice under risk or uncertainty
.
J Med Ethics
2014
;
40
:
774
778
.